ARISTOTLE
(c. 384 322 B.C.)
MODERATE
EMPIRICISM
Described by Dante
as "the master of them that know",
Aristotle is rightly regarded as one of the finest speculative and analytic
thinkers of all time. He was born at
Stagira in Thrace and studied under Plato at the Academy in Athens,
subsequently teaching there as Plato's colleague. After Plato's death in 347 he settled in
Mysia, and there he married Pythias, niece of a local ruler, and later moved to
Mitylene. In 343 he accepted an
invitation from Philip II of Macedon to tutor his young son Alexander the
future Alexander the Great. On returning
to Athens in 334 he established his own school, the Lyceum, in a sacred grove,
where he walked around (hence the name 'Peripatetic') each morning discussing
philosophy, while in the evening he lectured inside. After his wife's death he lived with Herpyllis,
who bore him a son Nicomachus. Falsely
accused of impiety by an anti-Macedonian faction he left Athens and settled in
Chalcis in 323. His scientific and
philosophical writings are encyclopaedic, covering the whole range of
contemporary human studies, but those which survive are for the most part
lecture notes rather than complete self-contained works.
[Sources: All page and line
references are to the standard Bekker edition of Aristotle's works and now
followed by most modern editions of individual texts.]
PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE/ METHODOLOGY
[1] In his Topics [Bk III]
Aristotle developed his ideas about dialectic. This is
essentially an activity which involves argument about various kinds of problems from premisses
or starting-points (archai) based on
people's opinions (endoxa) [a]. He said that this not
only exercises the mind but also can help us to argue effectively; and further
it can perhaps enable us to recognise truth and falsity and the first
principles of the sciences, that is, fields of knowledge. Aristotle's studies led him further to
investigate the formal structures underlying all reasoning, particularly the logic of propositions (a
proposition consisting of a subject term and a predicate term, linked by the
copula 'is') and the structure and rules of inference of the syllogism [see On Interpretation and Prior Analytics]. He was aware of the ambiguity of 'is' (estin), recognizing that it has both existential and a predicative uses [On Interpretation, ch. 11: 21a 24-33] [b]. He also distinguished between modal and non-modal propositions. The latter are those which just "say
something that applies", while the former say something either possibly or necessarily (that is
they cannot be other than true because they give the explanatory 'cause' [see secs 6 & 9] or
'essential nature'of something). [See Pr.
An. I, 2, 25a 1-2; Post. An. I,
2.]. (Non-modal and probable
propositions were later called assertoric; necessary propositions came to be
termed apodictic.). Non-modal
propositions as axioms are the premisses
of demonstrative or 'scientific' syllogisms, while modal ones are the axioms of
'dialectical' syllogisms [Post. An. I,
2; Topics 100a, 26-30]. Aristotle suggested that the concepts of necessity,
possibility, and contingency might be interdefinable by means of negation [c]. [See, for example, On Int.,
12, 13, & 21; Pr.An. I, 3, 13, 25
& 29.]
[2] Aristotle had some important things to say about truth,
language, and thought [see On
Interpretation, 1-3; Metaphysics G 3]. Aristotle seems to have
accepted some form of correspondence
theory of truth. Sometimes he regarded the predicates
'true' and 'false' as applying properly not to sentences but to inner
'thoughts', which would suggest a thought-to-world 'copying'
theory. Thus in On the Soul [ch.
6, 430b 27] he writes: "The thinking of
undivided objects is among those things about which there is no falsity. Where there is both falsity and truth, there
is already a combination of thoughts as forming a unity". This is because the actual words may vary
from language to language or with different speakers. To be called true or false a thought must be
expressed in a complete or composite sentence, that is, one which does not
consist of just a verb or a noun on its own even though such words may be
meaningful [cf. Categories, ch. 2]. But elsewhere it is clear that he
considered true statements
(expressions of thought) to be in some sense about objects in the real world
and the proper carriers of 'truth' and 'falsity [see Categories,
14b and Metaphysics, 1051b3][a]. Language for Aristotle is used primarily for 'interpretation'
(hermenetia) and at the level of speech [b]. "Spoken sounds", he writes, "are symbols of affections in the soul, and
written marks symbols of spoken sounds" [On Interpretation, 16a, 3-4 n
he here follows the account given in On the Soul (above)]. In so far as both the 'affections of the
soul' (that is, 'concepts') and the actual things these affections are
likenesses of are the same for everybody, language thereby 'interprets' in the
process of signifying the relationship of concepts to words and to things.
[3] Aristotle
distinguished different
kinds of sentences according to their functions in discourse [On Interpretation, chs 4, 6-9]. Declarative
('apophantic') sentences are used to make statements; other types to
give commands, ask questions, make requests, and so on. And he seems to have believed that only declarative sentences can
be true or false [a]. But not
every declarative sentence (or thought) has to be true or false. Certainly if a given statement is true, then
it cannot at the same time be false (the law of non-contradiction) [Posterior
Analytics I, 2, 72a 10ff.]; compare also: either P or not-P (the law of the excluded middle) [Metaphysics G 7]. But
he also seemed to suggest there are some statements, for example, statements about the future,
which are neither true nor false and which are therefore in breach of the principle of bivalence [b]. If we
fail to recognise this we can wrongly argue from a statement made now, say,
that there will be a sea-battle tomorrow (which may well turn out to have been
true) to the claim that the event will occur of necessity [see On Interpretation, ch. 9].
[4] [Categories 2] After examining different sorts of
expressions Aristotle divided reality (things in the world and the words we use
to talk about them) into four groups depending on the ways in which terms can
be regarded as predicable (that is, asserted of) or as being 'in' things (inseparable
from them). He then [Cat. 4] set out a list of ten ways in
which something can be said of a subject. These categories or 'predicables' relate to different sorts of
question one can ask [a]. Consider Socrates. We can say he
is a man (and hence an animal, since all men are animals). The individual Socrates is a particular and 'separable' thing who is
neither 'in' nor predicable of any other thing. He therefore belongs to the class primary
substance. Man and animal are
said to be secondary substances. 'Manness' is not 'in' Socrates, but it is in the real species that
Socrates is a member of, just as the species itself is included in the genus
animal. The other nine types of
predicables are qualities which are both in other things, that is, substances,
and can be asserted of them. They
are: quantity (for example, 1.5 metres
tall); quality (white); relation (double, larger than); place (in Athens); time
(yesterday); position (seated); possession (wearing shoes); activity (is
cutting); passivity (is being cut). For
Aristotle such categories
have being in derivative or analogical senses; only the
category of substance has being in the primary sense [b][b].
[5] Definition (horismos) [Categories,
ch. 1] What is definition? Before attempting to answer this question
Aristotle draws attention to the possibility of ambiguity. He discusses two kinds: (i) synonymy as
when different entities share the same name (for example, 'animal' may refer to
man, horse, dog, and so on); (ii) homonymy when a word has different meanings
(for example, 'plain'). He is
particularly concerned with the word 'esti'
('is'), from 'einai ('to be'), and
hence with 'being' a central concept in his metaphysics. Given such possible ambiguities there are, he
says [Posterior Analytics II, 13], difficulties with the view of
definition as a process of analysis (or 'division') of a genus into subgenera
by means of 'differentia' [a], for example, the definition of man (species)
as an animal (genus) characterized by being two-footed (difference). He does, however, allow a role to definition
by division in so far as (a) it ensures that we take the relevant
characteristics in the right order, and (b) enables us to determine when our
definition of the 'lowest species' (infima
species) has been reached. (In his
later writings [for example, Metaphysics,
Ζ 12 and Η 6] he modifies and expands on this account. To avoid problems raised by Plato's treatment of 'participation' of
genera and differentia [b] in the
Forms he appeals to the concepts of potentiality and actuality [b]. He supposes the genus exists potentially in the
species as its 'matter' on which the form of the lowest species is
imposed. Hence, he believes, a unity of
genus and differentia is achieved.) He
starts his own account of definition [Posterior
Analytics II, 9-10] by distinguishing between a nominal (or verbal) definition and a real (or 'essential')
one. The former relates to a
conventional usage in ordinary discourse what is signified by a name and
which may be an incomplete definition of a basic term in natural science, or a
definition of some event or quality as contained in the conclusion of a
syllogism (if we leave out the premisses). Real definitions,
however, give us an explanation of why and what a thing is [c]. This leads on to methodology.
[6] To discover real definitions we must make use of demonstration. Aristotle
says [Post. An. II, 1 and 2] that
before undertaking a demonstration we need to set out the objects of the enquiry,
that is, we have to know: what the name means; that the corresponding thing 'is'; that
it has such and such properties; and why it has them. There are also a number of requirements the
premisses (as archai) of a
demonstration must meet. They must be
true, primary, more 'intelligible', and prior to the conclusions we draw from
them; and they must be causes (aitiai 'explanatory factors') of the conclusions. He identifies four such factors: formal, material, efficient, and final [a] [see further in sec. 9 below]. Premisses, moreover, are of
several kinds. (1) There are axioms,
such as the principle of contradiction, in accordance with which our inferences
are drawn; and (2) theses or
'posits': these vary from science to
science. They include hypotheses and definitions. A hypothesis is
an assumption that something is or is not, whereas if we know what something is, or why it occurs we have a (real)
definition which, in the case of a primary substance, will give us its
material, formal, or final 'causes'. It is the aim of a given science
to reach such definitions. This
is done by constructing a scientific or
'cognitive' syllogism. Thus, suppose we
wish to define thunder [see Post. An. II, 10]. We must first produce the
nominal definition of the fundamental species by collecting common qualities
which we suppose are coextensive with and essential to it. For thunder one such quality is noise in the
clouds. (Here Plato's method of division
is relevant.) Aristotle's procedure (the epagoge) here is roughly what later came to be called inductive a move from particulars to
the universal. However, his account is not fully worked out
and is not always consistent [see Post.
An. II, 23]. Secondly, we search for
the reference of the middle term of the syllogism. 'Extinguishing of fire' is suitable here and
constitutes the efficient cause. Finally
the real definition thunder is a noise in the clouds caused by the
extinguishing of fire in them can be established when the complete syllogism
is constructed a deductive procedure of universal to
particular [b]. (This would not of course be regarded as the
correct explanation by scientists today.)
THE 'SCIENCES'
[7] Aristotle distinguishes three kinds
of 'science', that is, fields of human knowledge: (1) productive science, which involves the 'making' of things (for example, art, farming) we
might perhaps call it 'technology' (though not quite in the sense that we use
the term today; techne in Greek means
'skill'); (2) practical science
(ethics and politics); (3) theoretical science, whose goal is truth. He
subdivided the theoretical sciences into natural philosophy, mathematics, and
'theology'. Natural philosophy is
concerned with nature (phusis) n
material objects which are subject to change and motion, and thus includes
physics, chemistry and biology, as well as astronomy, which for Aristotle deals
with unchanging and material objects. None of these sciences is to be understood
precisely in the modern sense of the term. The objects of
mathematics are inseparable from matter but are themselves immaterial and not
subject to change [a]. As for metaphysics,
this is concerned generally with objects which are 'transcendent', that is, in
some sense distinct from matter, and unchanging. The supreme example of transcendent being or
'pure substance' for Aristotle is 'God' [b]. His 'special' metaphysics is
therefore called theology. (This is of course not be understood in the
standard, that is, Christian religious sense, though Aristotle's concept came
to be adapted for this purpose by mediaeval philosophers.) While many of his discussions of metaphysical
problems are found in his treatise called Metaphysics,
many issues we would regard as metaphysical are considered implicitly or
explicitly in other works. We have
already seen that he examines substance and predication in the Categories; and his treatment of change
and causation is to be found particularly in his Physics. (This will be
summarized under Philosophy of Nature.) Indeed it would seem that the Metaphysics was so called by commentators on Aristotle simply because it dealt with certain
philosophical problems arising out of previous discussions; 'metaphysics' comes
from the Greek for 'after the physics' (ta
meta ta physikon). In so far as it
is concerned with being in general, metaphysics for Aristotle is the primary science;
whereas the 'natural' or demonstrative sciences, which deal with facts and
principles derived from their own appropriate fundamental axioms, are 'lesser'
sciences though he accorded them a more important role than did Plato. And he rejected Plato's notion that they could all be derived from a primary set of axioms or
single principle, though he recognised that the various independent sciences
were analogous in their formal
procedures [c].
THEORETICAL SCIENCES
I. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE/COSMOLOGY
[8] In his Physics [I, 1-13] Aristotle seeks to provide a proper explanation of Nature and to
account for 'becoming' or change which he regards as real and can be
qualitative as well as positional or quantitative [see On Generation and Corruption, 325] [a]. He says [ch. 1] that the aim of empirical science is to discover the clear first
'explanatory' principles (archai) [b] underlying what we are already
acquainted with. Now, there cannot be
just one and unchanging principle, because principles have to be separate from
what they are to explain; and science needs change and plurality as real
phenomena. Monism, he argues [2 and 3]
is untenable because (1) it uses terms such as 'being' or 'to be', 'unity' or
'one' ambiguously (they are homonyms); (2) it is grounded in invalid arguments
or fallacious assumptions (for example, because everything which came into
being did not have a beginning). Are
there then many principles? Aristotle
says [5] that if there are, they must
consist in pairs of opposites so as to account for change Moreover [6], there
cannot be just a plurality; there also has to be some underlying
principle which is itself changing. His conclusion is that there must be at least two but not more than three principles [c].
He now has to deal with the problem of change. How could something have arisen either from
that which is or from that which is not?. To solve this he introduced [7-9] three 'principles' or factors which he supposed to be
involved in any change:. material substratum (hyle); form (morphe ) [d] ; and 'privation' [e]. He discusses first what he calls change as
alteration. Suppose we say of a man who acquires musical skills 'The unmusical becomes musical'. This seems to be a case of being coming from
non-being. However, if we reformulate
the assertion as 'A man becomes musical', we can see that a man as a persisting
entity a primary substance who previously lacked (the 'form' of)
musicality has now acquired it. In the case of substantial
change, say, when a statue is created from a piece of stone or bronze, what persists is the matter (the stone or bronze), the statue being the primary substance which has come
into being by virtue of the imposition of the form on the material substratum [d] a form which it previously lacked (the 'privation') [e].
[9] These two notions
are then [Physics II, 3, 7, 12]
linked to the two central concepts Aristotle uses in his natural philosophy,
namely, nature and 'explanatory item' or 'factor' (aition) which we referred to earlier as 'cause'. By 'nature' (physis)
he means that feature of a primary substance which gives it its special
character and which governs its behaviour [a]. This nature is at once active and passive in
that it both acts on itself and is acted on by itself. As for the aitia, these are factors which
enable us to account for, make sense of things and events. Thus they have an explanatory role [see sec. 8]. Aristotle lists four. (1) The constituent cause (traditionally called the material cause). Bronze can be regarded as such a cause in so
far as it accounts for various qualities a bronze statue may have, such as
colour and heaviness. (2) The essential (or formal) cause. This explains in some sense why a thing is
the kind of thing it is, and why it
functions in a particular way as that thing. Thus we might refer to the formal cause of an eye as that which accounts
for its shape and its capacity to receive images. (3) This is usually called the efficient cause 'initiatory cause' might be a better
term. The creator of the statue, the
sculptor, is such a cause; s/he starts the process and can change it. (4) The final cause. This relates to the end or
goal of a thing or process. Thus the
sculptor has an idea of what he wants to achieve and aims at bringing into
being. For Aristotle even inanimate
natural things may be supposed to have a final cause in that he thinks of such
things as undergoing a process of development in which their constituent parts
have a 'function' [see sec. 11]. He tends to reduce the four aitia to just two. His references to material causes reflect the
way he sees the natural
world as governed by mechanical necessity. The final cause can be assimilated to the formal cause, the two together pointing to emergent or
teleological processes in things [b], which are not necessitated by
external causes but are internally self-determining [b]. The efficient cause seems to have a role to
play in relation to both the material and formal-final 'dimensions' and thus in
effect connects the two. Although the various 'lesser' sciences differ from
each other both in their methods and in the objects they deal with, Aristotle
employs his 'explanatory factors' in each; and he stresses that all four are required if
explanation is to be 'adequate' and not just 'partial' [c][c]. This raises several interesting questions
concerning the scope of the 'causes' when applied to natural things in general.
[10] (1) Determinism
and freedom. Does Aristotle's
explanatory model suggest that what occurs in nature is inevitable? Is he a determinist? His discussion is not conclusive. Firstly, he does not wish to be committed to fatalism [a], as his discussion of the sea-battle
suggests [On Interpretation, ch. 9] n
though he has not actually proved that such events are not necessary. Secondly, he
admits that some events
are fortuitous [see Metaphysics E2; Physics II, 4-6, 8-9] [b]. This wil1 be the case when they occur (a) as an accidental consequence
of separate chains of causality, for, example, in the case of two people who
happen to meet in town; or (b) as a result of a causal change within a thing
which is not yet "contrary to nature" as when an animal gives birth to a
monster (we might nowadays attribute this to genetic mutation). If, in addition, the event could have been
the willed end of an adult human agent (Aristotle's views as to the
intellectual capacities of children were somewhat limited), this is described
as a matter of luck. An example is your
meeting someone by chance who owes you money and who happens to have just
received some money from someone else. Thirdly, he suggests [Post. An. II, 11; Physics VIII, 4; On the Parts of Animals I, 1] that the behaviour or mixtures (by
which he means homogeneous things like minerals, wood, and all organic, animate
beings) cannot be
completely accounted for solely in terms of their basic components, namely, the
four 'elements'. Thus he is not some
kind of 'reductionist' [c]. Moreover, human actions are intentional and purposive in a
sense he makes use of in his ethics, and he argues that individuals have control over their own actions [Ethics III] [d]. [See
further secs 18-21.]
[11] (2) [Physics II, 7-8.] What of final causation? Is not Aristotle committed also to the
importation of purpose and purposiveness into the inorganic, material realm? Indeed he speaks of natural motion as "seeking an end" in so far as it exemplifies a change of
potentiality towards actuality (unless interrupted by a chance natural event
which is not relevant to the realization of that end). Likewise he denies that, say, the formation
of rain in the clouds and its falling onto the crops is a matter of chance and
lacking regularity. The process thus
seems to be 'purposive', for some end. "Nature", he says, "does nothing in vain, nothing superfluous" [On the Heavens A4]. But this need not imply some deliberate intention
or will in the stronger sense, say, of Nature itself or of 'God'. His point is that, although not designed or intended, natural events
may still have a 'purpose' in the sense of function [a]. By
'function' of an item or event he means that it is to be understood in terms of
the role it plays in the larger whole. For example, today we know that the 'job' of the heart is to pump blood
around the body and thus sustain the life of the organism by distributing
oxygen to and removing carbon dioxide from the cells. The organism itself might also be said to
have a function in relation to the wider environment [see Ethics below]. Thus for Aristotle things and events can be
accommodated within an explanatory framework which is both mechanical (material
'cause' how the rain comes into being) and teleological (efficient →
formal → final 'cause' how it serves some 'end, namely, to make the
corn grow). It would seem
therefore that he admitted
different 'levels' of explanation appropriate to different kinds of situations
or objects [b].
[12] Cosmology /theology. Aristotle discusses motion, time and the void (or space) in his Physics III and IV. Motion, he says, occurs when, as the result
of the removal of external constraints, natural bodies are enabled to exercise
their innate power to bring about change [a]. Change of position in a body may also happen when another body
impacting on it passes on the "power to move". (This decreases with distance.) Motion presupposes both time and place. Aristotle defines space
as the 'inner limit' of the body which 'contains' it [b]. He thinks there are absolute places (for
example, up and down) for the four elements to exist in. Time is that real feature of the
created world of real movement (alteration of size, appearance, position) through which the mind can recognise that changes
are occurring ; and it is eternal in so far as that which moves (the material
realm) is eternal. But he wonders
whether there could be time if there were no souls to do the measuring of
movement [Phys. IV, 223a
21ff.] [c]. Actually existing spatio-temporal bodies, says Aristotle, cannot be
infinite; they could be neither composite, nor simple, nor have a surface, nor
occupy an absolute position. But he does
admit the idea of theoretical infinite divisibility of both space and
time. In On the Heavens he says all the things of the universe form a scale of being [d]. At the bottom is inorganic matter, then
organic matter, namely, plants, animals, and man. Our earth is at the centre of the universe and is surrounded by several
layers of the other three fundamental 'elements' water, air and fire,
all of which makes up the sublunary sphere (where things move in straight
lines), but which
themselves have no explanatory value. Around this sphere is the superlunary sphere of the stars, which is composed of a fifth 'element', aether [d]. The
motion of the stars is circular. This outermost sphere gets its
motion (and thus time) from the Prime (and unmoved ) Mover or 'God' the
eternally existing, necessary, self-knowing, living and transcendent Nous, "the thought that
thinks" (noesis noeseos) [Metaphys. XII (Λ,), 1074b,
33-5], which is pure form and the first and final cause (and
thereby the efficient cause) of change. Aristotle says there
must be a first principle because there can be no infinite series of causes,
and he regards the world as eternal and as necessary by virtue of the necessity
of the Prime Mover [Metaphys. a ii; Phys. VIII, 5] [e]. He regarded
Anaxagoras's notion of Mind as the possible ultimate cause as a step in the
right direction but inadequate [e], because it was nothing more than a kind of deus
ex machina dragged in to produce order "when he is at a loss to explain a
necessary result. Otherwise he makes
anything rather than Mind the cause of what happens" [Metaphys. I (A),
4: esp. 984b15]. Aristotle's argument for the existence of the Prime Mover or eternal
substance from our experience of the circular motion of the heavens (which epitomizes eternal change and time as against the perishability of all
other substances) is a
version of what Kant referred to as the
'cosmological argument' [see Metaphysics L, 6-8; Physics VIII, 6]. (The other spheres get their
rotatory motion from incorporeal beings subordinate to God) [e]. Another approach to
the question of the existence of a prime mover appeals to a 'gradation of
truth/being' [f]. This is suggested by Aristotle's
seventh 'negative' proof of the law of contradiction where he argues that if that which has more of any quality is nearer its norm, there should be some truth to which the 'more true' is nearer [Metaphysics G, 4: 1008b31 1009a5]. "[The cause] which imparts to other things a
certain character itself has that character in the highest degree" [Met. a, I. This book was a later
insertion into the Metaphysics see Ross, p. 13]. As for the moral condition of the world, he
argues that, while not
intrinsic to the cosmos, evil is associated with individual things as a kind of
by-product as they strive towards greater actuality and perfection [see Metaphysics Q, 9; also sec. 20] [g]. As he says, "the bad does not exist apart from bad things; for the bad
is in its nature posterior to the potentiality" [1051, 18].
II. METAPHYSICS
[13] [Metaphysics Z 1-3.]. A thing may be said to 'be' in a
variety of ways, but its primary sense is the 'what' which indicates the substance (ousia) of the thing rather than the 'that' it is. For Aristotle essence and existence, although distinct, are inseparable; whatever is 'real' exists [a]. However, it is prior in definition, time, and
knowledge. Being qua being
is in fact the central concern of his metaphysics [a]. He regards it as special because all other modes of
being are dependent on it. So many
thinkers in the past, he says [2] have proposed as substances either 'sensible'
things (animals and their parts, the elements, for example) or non-sensible
things (Plato's Forms, mathematical objects). How are we to decide? What we
need to find is some 'mark' or test by which we can identify substantiality
[30]; and he examines three possibilities.
(1) [Z 3] Substance cannot be simply a bare unqualified
'subject', that is, a material substratum or support for properties; for then
it would be unknowable. So what
is wanted is a way of pinning down the 'thisness' or individuality of a thing n
that which makes it a "this so-and-so" (tode
ti).
(2) Could it then be 'essence' (ti en
einai what it is to be something)? Now, being musical, say, or even having bones and flesh is not essential
to one's being what one is. In fact the
only things which have their own properties essentially are species; and they
are things whose 'formula of their meaning' [1030c16] is given by a real
definition. So when we refer to Socrates
as being a man this is to talk of him as having an essential property by virtue
of his belonging to the species man;
whereas as an individual he may be supposed also to possess accidental
properties (such as being pale). Thus it
would seem that the species
is a substance because of the essentiality criterion [b]. Aristotle takes the discussion further [7-9] by considering the
possibility that form has substantiality (and interestingly he now uses the
same term eidos for both 'species'
and 'form' previously morphe). He reintroduces [7] the distinction he had made
in the Physics [I, 7] between
immanent form and matter and argues that it is the form in the composite nature (phusis) of form and matter which
constitutes its primary and unitary substantiality [c] makes it what it is. This is the so-called doctrine of hylomorphism
— but applicable only to corporeal beings [c].
(3) Aristotle also then [13] considers and rejects the view that substances
are universals (including genera), both being interpreted by him as Platonic
separable Forms or 'essences' [d][d]. The basis of his objection is that if this universal were to be a
substance it would have to be the substance either of all individuals or of
none both of which options he disallows. He also points out that, while substance is not predicable of a
subject, the universal always occurs as
the predicate term and indicates a 'such' and not a 'this'. Aristotle suggests other arguments and later
[14 and 15] sets out a number of criticisms of Plato's doctrine of the Forms and its absurd
consequences. Separate Forms, for example, could not initiate
motion in the sensible things to which they are prior (ante rem), and would contribute nothing to the being of such things
or to our knowledge of them [e][e]. Separable Forms would also require there to be many Forms within, say, a man, each corresponding to
one of his parts. These Forms would have
to be substances, and the man would be different from his parts. Aristotle also criticizes the theory that attributes reality to numbers
and identifies Forms with them [f]. And he refers to the 'Third Man' argument. His general conclusion is that there can be
no separable Forms and that universals cannot be substances. Substantiality must therefore lie in immanent
essence.
In Metaphysics Δ, 7 Aristotle introduces a distinction between existence or being in its own right and
'coincidental' existence [g]. Actual existents are individuals or accidents though the latter cannot
exist separate from individual beings. Thus Socrates and his paleness are both actual existents. However, things are said to 'be'
coincidentally when they hold good of the same 'thing-that-is'. This may involve predicating an accident of an accident (as
when we say that someone pale is artistic), or predicating an accident of a
subject (for example, a man is artistic), or predicating a subject of an
accident (someone artistic is a man). Similarly a complex such as 'Socrates is pale' is qua that complex a coincidental and not an actual existent.
[14] Aristotle's thesis in the Metaphysics can be summarized as
follows. An individual, say, Socrates is a composite of matter and
form. It is this 'essential' or 'species
form' of 'humanness' which determines
that Socrates belongs to the species (or kind) of human being, that is, makes
him a man. Such 'species forms' are thus
substances in some primary sense. Being
a man is Socrates' essential property the 'formula' given by the real
definition, "the formula of its meaning" [1030a16]. And as Aristotle says, "There is an essence
only of those things whose formula is a definition" [1030a5]. But there is now a problem. In the Categories he had argued that it is individual things, that is, things which in the Metaphysics are called composites of
matter and form, that are primary substances, species such as man being
substantial only in a secondary derived sense. He does point out [1030a18-20] that the notion of definition is
ambiguous: in one sense it means
substance and a 'this', whereas in another sense it means one or other of the
predicates. Nevertheless it is
questionable whether the Categories account can be reconciled with that presented in the Metaphysics. A solution may
lie in his use [Metaphysics Θ 7;
see also D 7 1017b] of the concepts of
potentiality and actuality introduced in his Physics [see sec. 5 above]. [See
Lear, ch. I.]. In Metaphysics Z 17 he argues that there must be some principle of
unity over and above form and matter which keeps these two components
together. Take the example of the bronze
sphere [see H 6]. This is not a single definable unity; and this is because the matter of
the bronze is only a potential existent. Before being made into a
sphere, or a statue, the bronze had certain non-substantial properties, and it
is these that now exist in actuality in the sphere. The bronze itself,
however, is not actually present and does not therefore break up the unity of
the form and matter of the sphere. Thus
Aristotle can now claim that both the unitary composite and the 'species form'
are substantial entities, the latter giving substantiality to the former. So we can say that for him an individual thing is a
composite of matter, the physical stuff (as pure potentiality), and form, the
individual's essence (as actuality) [a][a]. Individuals belonging to the same species possess the same form or essence, but this form is numerically different : it is not one (Platonic) Form
instantiated in different individuals. Now, because the formal aspect is the same in all individuals belonging to a given
species (for example, man), it must be the material aspect which makes the
individuals (Socrates, Callicles) different. It is therefore the
(potential) matter that is said to be the principle or factor of individuation [a]. At the same time, Aristotle says, it is the form which actualizes the material aspect and makes
it into an individual thing. Thus
his position seems to be that a primary substance (in the 'everyday' or 'scientific' sense of
individual thing) is produced by virtue of the 'actualizing' role of the form
(primary substance in the metaphysical sense) on the relative material
potentiality (both of which compose the individual) [b][b]. The essential form thus exists in the thing (in rem) [c].
III. PSYCHOLOGY
[15] The term
'psychology' is not to be understood in its modern sense; for Aristotle it is
the 'science' of the 'soul' (psuche). There has been much debate about the meaning of this word in his
writings. In his early work (Eudemus) his account seems to have been
similar to that proposed by Plato in the Timaeus,
whereas in his mature On the Soul his
view reflects both his empirical research in biology and the analyses of form
and matter he had attempted to work out in the Metaphysics. However, there
is now broad agreement among scholars that throughout his academic life
Aristotle held to a view of the soul as in some sense substantial and
unitary. So what does this mean in On the Soul? He devotes Book I firstly to a discussion of
how the concept of the soul fits in to the wider context of the 'sciences' and
then, secondly, to a critical
examination of some of the theories which had been put forward by his
predecessors in particular the
materialist accounts of some Presocratics and the so-called 'harmony' view [a] (which Plato himself had criticized in
the Phaedo), largely on the grounds
that they fail to account for the 'motivating' power of the soul, that is, its
capacity to influence or bring about changes in physical things. Aristotle's own position is developed in Book
II. He starts [II, 1] by defining the soul as "the first entelechy
[or actuality] of a natural organic body". By this he means that, as the 'principle of life', it
'informs' and thereby actualizes the material body, making it a living thing (empsuchon soma 'ensouled' body). It
is thus both formal and final 'cause'. The soul is thus the 'essential' attribute of a living thing, the body
providing its other attributes the ensouled body constituting the unitary human substance [b]. He says [II, 2 and 3] there are three grades or
'parts' of soul [c] These seem to exist in a kind of hierarchy.
The lowest is the nutritive soul, possessed by plants, which
underlies reproduction and the taking in of nourishment [4]. Animals too have this soul but in addition
they possess a sensitive soul, which
makes possible. such functions as sense-perception, desire, and local movement
— all of which contribute to the organism's survival and well-being [5]. The various senses and their objects are
examined in II, 6-11, and perception is treated in II,12 and III. Man's soul is the
highest of all. As well as assimilating
the functions of the nutritive and sensitive souls, it is characterized by
reason or intellect (nous), which gives to man his capacity
for both theoretical and practical
thinking. [III, 4 n6.] Aristotle
distinguishes between an active nous (to poioun) and a passive intellect nous pathetikos. It would seem that he regarded the active intellect as an
actuality, identical in all individuals to the extent that it is, arguably, a
manifestation of divine intellect, and
as at least conceptually separable from the passive intellect and the body [d][d]. As to the question of the
soul's immortality, he may have held the view that reasoning and memory are essentially functions of
the composite being (matter and form) and that therefore active reason cannot
survive the body's death; or that if it does then at most it exists as a
principle devoid of content. However, in his On the Generation
of Animals he refers to the active intellect as having come in "from
outside" [736b], while in On the Soul [405a] he also says it is
immortal and eternal in itself, without memory, unaffected by its embodiment [e]. He also argues [De Anima III, 10] that the 'motivating' capacity of the
soul, is to be attributed a faculty which is both rational and volitional (he
calls it 'desiderative thought' or 'intellectual desire' [Ethics VI, 2 1139b4] ) — the two aspects constituting
(preferential, or moral) choice [ibid., III, ch. 2] [f]. If we leave aside the active
intellect a concept which, it has to be admitted, sits uneasily with his
overall position we can say that
Aristotle's account of the soul and 'ensouled
bodies' as living things avoids both materialism and Platonic dualism. [His accounts of perception and concept
formation through the agency of the intellect will be considered in the context
of his theory of knowledge.]
IV. KNOWLEDGE
[16] Knowledge for Aristotle
is, in a strict sense, of the universal and of what is 'necessary' or
'essential' [a]. He does, however, also talk of two kinds of knowledge (episteme) of being potential (of the universal and 'indefinite')
and actual (of 'definite' particulars) [Metaphysics, 1087a] [a]. Such particulars are
either the individual things we are aware of through the senses or contingent
facts which we have acquired or been taught and which are grounded in sense perception [a]. This raises two issues: (1) how knowledge in the strict sense is
achieved from sense perception as the starting point; and (2) how Aristotle
distinguishes between knowledge and belief (or opinion
— doxa) [a].
(1) Sense perception [On the Soul II, 5-11; III, 1; On the Senses, 7]. Rejecting any appeal to
recollection or 'innate' knowledge, Aristotle says knowledge, although
requiring intellect, starts from sense-perception. To account for this he introduces the idea of
a general faculty of 'common sense' [b][b]. This manifests itself
through specialized faculties corresponding to the various sense organs. Thus the eye perceives colour, the hand feels
heat. Several organs may be involved in
instances of 'unspecialized' or common perceptions, as when, for example, size,
shape, or movement are perceived by both sight and touch. Common sense is required for distinguishing
between the objects of different senses and for simultaneous perceptions. Aristotle also refers to 'incidental'
perceptions. We may see a white object
(to see a colour is 'essential') but also see it as the son of Cleon (this is incidental not
essential). Sense perception for Aristotle is not a purely
passive process. He regards it as an
actualizing of potentiality (this
being the faculty possessed by the sense organ): the eye itself becomes white when it sees the
white object, the hand becomes hot. This actualizing involves a
'reception of form' without the matter of the perceived object [c][c] ("much as
wax takes the sign from the ring without the iron and gold" [On the Soul II, 12]. How then does sense
perception lead to knowledge? When we perceive a particular
object we are perceiving characteristics which it possesses in common with
other things (universals in rebus n
'in things') [d]. Perceiving an object leaves an image in the soul through the operation
of the faculty of imagination (phantasia) [see On the Soul III, 3]. And in knowing an
object the mind thereby knows itself as the active knower [cf. Metaphysics Λ, 1072, 20ff] [d]. In memory we become aware of this image as relating to something
past [see On Memory 1 and 2]. With repetition of memory images
or impressions we acquire 'experience' through universal concepts of objects (post rem 'after the thing'). It is the active intellect that is involved
when the common characteristic is received or 'abstracted' from the perceived
object. And he says that this characteristic (the form) is received in the soul in accordance with the mode of the
receiving intellect [e] [cf. On the Soul III, 4 & 8]. It is from these universal
concepts that we can move to the highest unanalysable universals or
definitions, which are apprehended or intuited by nous. Herein lies genuine
knowledge [see Posterior Analytics,
II, 19] [e].
[17] (2) Knowledge and belief [Post.
An., I, 33]. In a general or loose
sense we do of course have knowledge (gnosis)
of particular things. When we perceive a
cloud, say, are we not certain that we are seeing something white? Do we not know that man is an animal? Aristotle argues that, strictly speaking, genuine knowledge [a] can be achieved only through application of the
scientific method to sensory data [a][a] [see also sec. 16 above, and cf. sec. 1]. Perception must
involve judgement [b][b], and this opens up the possibility of error, of
contingency. Two people may judge that
man is an animal, but while the one may regard this as an incidental attribute
the other has identified animality as man's essence. The mental state of the former is that of opinion: only the latter can be said to truly know [c][c]. Even to say an object is seen to be white
involves the fallible judgement that there is a real thing of some sort, not
just a chimera or illusion. Perhaps
there is little or no chance of error if we confine ourselves to the bare
seeing of white as such: but Aristotle
seems to suggest that this is a purely passive state that involves no
judgement. Such limiting particularity
cannot therefore provide us with knowledge in the strict sense.
PRACTICAL SCIENCES
I. ETHICS
NATURALISTIC TELEOLOGY
[18] Aristotle's moral
philosophy, as set out in the Nicomachean
Ethics, is teleological (directed towards an end). But he
is critical [I, 6] of certain feature's
of Plato's ethics. (1) He rejects the notion of a
'universal' Good and the view that it can be directly 'known' [a]. There cannot be one Form embracing both the absolutely and the
relatively good [a]. (2) In any case, 'good' is used in a variety of ways [b] according
as to whether it describes reasons or things, qualities or excellences of
things, ends or a means to those ends. (3) The end which men seek is not a static knowledge of the Good; rather
it is a good which is more aptly described as an activity. What then is Aristotle's own positive
account?
[I, 7-12] Every deliberate action, he says, is directed towards the attaining of some end. This end is equated by Aristotle with the good. But. there are many different ends, corresponding to different activities; and some of these ends are but means to achieving more ultimate ends. For example, the doctor gives medicine to
help his patient to sleep, and this is conducive to health. Aristotle argues that there is an end which we, as moral agents, seek
only for its own sake. This is 'happiness' or 'well-being' (eudaimonia) and is the absolutely
good [c]. Other ends, such as honour and
pleasure may of course be desired for their own sake, but also because they are
perceived as a means to achieving eudaimonia. What then is happiness? It is neither
pleasure nor honour; nor is it virtue, because a virtuous person can be
unhappy, though clearly virtue is desirable. Aristotle finds his answer in the
concept of function or appropriate activity. Now just as it is the job
of a knife to cut so it is
man's function to be rational; and this may be exhibited in both the
theoretical and practical spheres. The rational man will follow a certain way of life which may be
characterized as an activity of his soul when following a rational principle or ground of the action. The job of a good man is to perform this
function well, that is, when performed
with the excellence or virtue proper to it. Life for the virtuous soul is intrinsically happy. Aristotle notes (a) that our happiness, in
the last analysis, depends on our own performance of virtuous actions (whatever
gifts we may possess from birth or upbringing); (b) that well-being should be judged in
the context of one's life as a whole [d],
taking account of the occasional misfortune most of us suffer.
[19] [II and IV] What exactly
does he mean by 'virtue'? He distinguishes between moral virtues and
intellectual virtues.
Moral virtues:. Moral virtue as such is to be identified
neither with our feelings nor with the faculties we have for feeling, because
they are not proper objects of praise or blame. Moreover, our faculties are
acquired from nature whereas it is not nature that makes us good or bad. So he defines moral virtue (or excellence) as a disposition or state of
the soul [a] "concerned
with choice, lying in a mean relative to us, this being determined by reason
and in the way in which the man of practical wisdom would determine it" [II, 6;
1107a]. This doctrine of the mean (to mesos) the 'middle term', belonging
to all virtues — is central in Aristotle's ethics. At the end of
Book II he applies it to particular virtues. Nous, for example, in the case of feelings inspired by danger courage is the mean state between rashness
(excess) and cowardice (deficiency). It should be stressed that Aristotle is
not talking here of an absolute mean (as 6 is the mean between 2 and 10) but a relative mean: the right measure of
feeling or action is what is appropriate
in the particular circumstances of time, motive, and so on [b]. Of special importance is
Aristotle's account of justice
as a moral virtue. He in fact
makes a distinction between a universal sense
of the term [V, 11] and a narrower, particular sense [V, 2]. In the universal sense justice (dike) is identified with virtue in general in a social context. In the
narrower particular sense, however,
justice (isotes) is said to be a specific virtue. Particular justice in
turn is divided into distributive justice
[V, 2-3] and corrective justice [V, 4], both of which involve a proportionality but, respectively, geometrical and arithmetical. What Aristotle means by this can be
shown by examples. Distributive justice is
concerned with fairness. Suppose
two people are quarrelling about, say, money. How the money should be shared depends on the individuals and what they
own. A rich man should receive a smaller
share, a poor man a larger. The proportions are therefore relative: if the
amounts are too great or too small then
there is injustice. Corrective justice, however, is
independent of the circumstances. Sharing must be equal between
loss and gain. Particular justice is
thus a mean, geometrical or arithmetical, between extremes [c]..
[20] Intellectual virtues. What are these? According to Aristotle [VI] they are the qualities the soul
requires to discover the rules or principles enabling it to act virtuously [a] when it collaborates (rather than being
just in conformity) with them. He
distinguishes five 'modes' by which the soul can
attain to truth. (1) Science (episteme) is "a habit of mind with an aptitude for demonstration". Scientific knowledge is attained
deductively from first premisses which are given to us through and are known to be certain [b][b]. (2) Art (techne) [c] This is the productive faculty [c]: "a rational faculty exercised in making (poeisis) something". (3) Prudence (phronesis) is the
'calculative' faculty [d]: "a rational faculty exercised for the
attainment of truth in things that are humanly good or bad". Without prudence
it is not possible to be good. (4) Intelligence or Speculative Wisdom (nous) is the activity by means of which we
grasp the truth of first principles and truth in reasoning generally [e]. (5) Wisdom (sophia). This
is obtained through the combination of Intelligence and Science and is
"employed on the grandest subjects of contemplation" [f]. It is, says Aristotle, the kind of knowledge which
comes closest to perfection. In this way
we can approximate to the life of the eternal living God.
[21] There are several
particular problems arising out of his ethics that Aristotle examines. The first (I, 4) concerns how we become virtuous. We are not born naturally good, and neither
can we learn virtue as such. Rather we
have the capacity to acquire the moral and intellectual virtues. Our choices and nature work together they
are 'corresponsible' or 'part-causes' (sunaitioi pos) for forming the
dispositions which make up our character [1114b 20-25]. We gain knowledge, prudence, wisdom through study. But we become just by performing just actions. It might seem that there is some circularity
here: how can we perform a just action if we are not already virtuous? However, Aristotle's view is that in so far
as an action is right, that is, appropriate to the circumstances, performing it
in the recognition that it is right, and with a good motive, we shall acquire
and then strengthen the disposition within ourselves to act justly. Virtue as such cannot be taught directly but we can be told when we are
young what is virtuous and here we may rely on the experience of the wise or
prudent (to phronimos) [a].
A second problem concerns weakness
of will [III and VII]. Praise or
blame is appropriate only in the case of voluntary actions, that is actions which presuppose choice in the thinking and
desiring of some end, and in the deliberation about the means to attain
it. Aristotle says that involuntary
actions are those which (a) are performed solely under external compulsion, or
(b) result from the agent's ignorance of the particular circumstances (as opposed to his general ignorance of, say, the law). Thus we should not blame a
ship's captain who has been forced by mutineers to do something
dishonourable. As for the second ground
for exoneration, an example is of a person who gives someone food without
knowing it has been poisoned, unless his ignorance is due to his having been
negligent or perhaps drunk. So why do
people, given free choice, ever do bad actions? Aristotle's view is that the incontinent or weak-willed person does wrong either because his
knowledge is 'latent', that is, not fully activated, or because he is overcome
by passion [b]. Such people, he says, just happen to be like
that; they lack practical wisdom. It
would therefore be inconsistent to withhold blame in such a case if we did not
also withhold praise from the morally strong person who can develop his knowledge and cultivate practical reason, and does
not give into temptation.
Thirdly, the fact that the primary motivation of the individual
as a moral agent is to seek his own
'well-being' might suggest that Aristotle's ethics is somewhat egoistic. He himself was aware of this. Others are of course acknowledged in his
concept of justice and in his political philosophy [sec. 22]. And in the Nicomachean Ethics [esp. Books VIII, chs 3 & 5; IX, 4 and 8] the problem is addressed in his
discussion of friendship. He
distinguishes first between 'friendships of utility', 'friendships of pleasure', and 'friendships
of goodness' [VIII, 3]. With respect to
the last he argues [IX, 4] that the good
man has a relation to himself , or rather, between his several 'elements' or
'parts' (the primary one being the intellectual see sec. 15), and that this relation may be characterized by such
marks of friendship as disinterestedness and sympathy. Now a friend is in a sense another self; and
so the friendship between two people is seen to possess the same
characteristics. He also argues, more
convincingly [VIII, 5] that to love one's friends is to love one's own good;
for the good man by the very act of becoming another's friend becomes that
other's good. Encompassing the other's
wellbeing is thereby an extension of one's interests. This is compatible with 'good' self-love (philautia) though
one can of course love oneself in the crude selfish sense [c].
II. POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
[22] Aristotle is very much concerned with the structure and order of human
society. Like
Plato, he regarded the city-state, the polis, as providing the context in which man might best flourish,
fulfil his proper 'function', and achieve the 'good-life' and 'well-being' [a][a]. It
is because of this that he says [Politics 1253a] man is a political
('social') animal (zoon politikon) [b]. But Aristotle's view of
the state differed from Plato's in
important respects. Firstly, he rejected Plato's 'communism' [c]. He placed much greater emphasis on the
family, which he regarded as the fundamental biological unit, and he also had a
more positive attitude towards private property, regarding possessions as
desirable and conducive to the virtuous life provided moderation is exercised
in their use and 'goods' are not accumulated for their own sake. Secondly, while Plato tended to have a
negative view of law, seeing it as the means whereby the philosopher-rulers
might paternalistically control and direct the other two classes, Aristotle
tended to encourage the fullest participation of citizens in the running of the polis. Citizenship, however, did not extend to women or slaves, both groups
according to Aristotle being 'by nature' inferior and therefore subject to the
rule of others, though he did insist that they be treated properly and allowed
that a slave might in time gain his or her freedom.
So as to develop his own account of
political science Aristotle commissioned a detailed investigation of no less
than 158 constitutions. These fall into
two main groups: (1) states which aim at
the good of all; (2) those in which power is concentrated in the hands of a
single person or group concerned with its own private welfare. To the first group belong monarchy,
aristocracy and 'polity'; while
corresponding to these there are in the second group tyranny (rule by one man),
oligarchy (rule by the few), and democracy (rule by the people the
many). In general Aristotle argues that
monarchy is the ideal form though only in theory because there are no
individuals who are superior to other citizens in wisdom and virtue. Even an aristocracy is not easy to establish. So he realistically settles for a 'polity'. This is in effect a constitution combining
the best features of democracy and oligarchy and in which ideally his principle of justice might be applied [d]. Many citizens are
involved in running the state's affairs, but they are normally only those who
by reason of their wealth and property have the leisure needed for active
participation in politics. The members
of this middle class of 'equals' perform the various necessary judicial and
administrative tasks.
PRODUCTIVE SCIENCES
AESTHETICS/PHILOSOPHY OF ART
[23] Aesthetic issues
are discussed in Aristotle's Poetics. Art in general (techne) is called 'poetical' because it is concerned with producing
or creating (poesis) something. Aristotle divides it into (a) tool-making
(which completes the 'work' of Nature) and (b) fine art, the function of which is to imitate or represent Nature. By this he means the 'catching' and
translating of the universal in things into dramatic poetry, sculpture, music,
as the case may be [a]. He identifies three kinds of drama: epic, tragic, and comic. Tragedy is particularly important in that through it the playwright seeks to
portray good actions and life in such a way so as to arouse and release the
emotions of pity and fear in the spectators as well as himself. He refers to this by the medical term catharsis (purgation) [ Poetics 1449b, 28] [b]. However, there is some debate as to what his full explanation of this
process was, as the relevant section of the book is lost. In his Politics he refers to it as an
action comparable to that to that produced by 'orgiastic' music: listeners are firstly excited and then
restored to tranquillity. They undergo
"a kind of purgation and relief accompanied by pleasure" [Politics,
1340a, 1342a]. The action of the
tragedy was supposed to act on the plot or characters and on the spectators in
a similar fashion. (Commentators
disagree as to whether Aristotle's view was that pity and fear were removed
after the 'purging' or whether they remained the suggestion being that
Aristotle was concerned only with removing 'excessive' emotion.) He asserts further that the beauty of a tragic drama is judged by two criteria: order (the ordered arrangment of its
incidents or actions, constitutes the
plot), and 'definiteness' or 'limitation' (the work should be neither too large
nor too small). Well-ordered plots also
exhibit a unity; they have a beginning, a middle, and an end [Poetics,
1450b, 27-33] [c]. In the case of other
types of art Aristotle also adds symmetry or proportionality as a third
criterion [see Metaphysics 1078, 36].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
While there are obvious surface differences
between Aristotle and his teacher Plato we might say, for example, that much
of Aristotle's surviving work is more 'condensed' and 'technical', and that he
paid greater attention to 'ordinary' or everyday linguistic usage; or that he
is perhaps less 'visionary' or idealistic than Plato nevertheless both
philosophers were concerned with similar issues:. appearance and reality, the concept of form
(or the 'Forms'), change and permanence, mind ('soul') and body, virtue and
justice, and what constitutes the 'good' life for man, to name but a few. Indeed throughout the mediaeval era, from
Augustine to Ockham, most thinkers, in their own approach to these problems
(and having regard to the demands of reason as well as faith), felt it
necessary to integrate into their philosophies elements from both Plato and
Aristotle albeit with varying degrees of emphasis and selectivity. Many of
them also tended to interpret Aristotle as having produced a 'grand system'
— despite the evident inconsistencies in
his thought. To some extent these can be explained on the assumption that his
writings were collections of lectures put together in a somewhat arbitrary
fashion by his successors. But it is still a matter of on-going debate as to
whether there is any obvious development in his philosophy. Some commentators
have argued in favour of a progressive move away from Plato; while others have
suggested that after initial penetrating criticism of his teacher's doctrines
he tended to take up a more sympathetic position. That his philosophy was not static, that
there are differences of emphasis if not in hard content, is, however,
incontrovertible. Moreover, even though
Aristotle was a "super-genius" (as Ackrill calls him), his solutions to many of
the central problems he addressed are still open to objections.
(1) Philosophy of logic and language. Aristotle assumes that to analyse the terms we use to describe the world
is to reveal its actual structure. This assumption has been contested by some
recent philosophers. His list of
categories or predicates also seems to be arbitrary. Moreover he seems not to have thought through
fully the distinctions that can be made between sentences, statements and
propositions; and this probably underlies his treatment of the predicates
'true' and 'false' and of statements about the future. However, in his defence it might be said that
such 'weaknesses' are hardly surprising given that he was working on these
matters some 2500 years ago and in some respects limited by the Greek language
of his day. Indeed it is to his greater
credit that he was nevertheless able to produce philosophy of such prescience
and analytical power. As for his
contribution to formal logic, some critics have argued that his syllogistic
logic is flawed, (a) because it lacks the scope and flexibility of, say, modern
predicate calculus; and (b) it does not lead to new knowledge in the way
Aristotle supposes in his account of scientific methodology. These are fair comments, but in reply it can be said that while syllogistic logic is indeed in
some respects limited and incomplete this is in no way detracts from its power
as a consistent and coherent axiomatic system. As to the second criticism, it should be said that if this point is
valid it is not unique to Aristotle but
a. feature of deductive logic in general.
(2) Metaphysics. The major
features in Aristotle's metaphysics are undoubtedly his subtle analysis of the
concept of substance and his hylomorphism. The major problem perhaps is the seemingly unresolved tension between
his identification of primary substance firstly with the individual composite
of form and matter and secondly with the 'essential form' which is 'actualizes'
the individual from its material potentiality. Aristotelian scholars continue to debate this issue and much turns on
how exactly the relevant writings should be interpreted. Moreover, it remains an open question as to
whether Aristotle regarded both prime matter and 'pure' form (in the case of
the 'active intellect' and God) as having actual independent existence. The notions of 'essence' and individuation,
and Aristotle's criteria for the identity of a particular thing are also all
still live issues; his solutions can by no means be accepted as satisfactory.
(3) Methodology. Although through
painstaking observation and classification Aristotle made an outstanding
contribution to biology, he was not of course an experimental scientist in the
modern sense, and understandably by today's standards his methodology is
flawed. There is no recognition in his
writings of the confirmation or falsification procedures required if knowledge
of the workings of nature is to be obtained. For him knowledge is located in 'real definitions' which give the
'essences' of things they purport to 'explain' what and why a thing is what
it is. They should not be seen as
general principles or laws testable against experience. However, his use of the four aitiai,
('causes' or 'explanatory factors') is undeniably original and fertile and
marks an advance on Plato though the concept of the aitia sits uneasily
between our contemporary usage of 'cause' and 'explanation', and his analysis
should not be accepted uncritically. Nevertheless, he anticipates modern methods to the extent that his
methodological framework allows for both inductive and deductive processes. It
has been objected further that there is often an inconsistency between his
teleological and mechanistic explanations. But it is possible to interpret 'purpose' and 'purposiveness' in biology
in a purely functional sense without invoking conscious deliberation or
intentional aims.
(4) Mind. Aristotle's
hylomorphism leads to difficulties with his account of mind (or soul psyche). On the question of the soul's survival after
the body's death his writings are equivocal. Could there be a form existing independent of matter? What is the status of the 'active
intellect'? (And indeed in what sense
can God be understood as pure form?) Many mediaeval philosophers grappled with these issues not least
because of their commitment to Christian dogma. However, most modern commentators argue that Aristotle was concerned not
so much with solving this problem (and the problem of what constitutes
consciousness) as to develop "a coherent conceptual framework within which the
phenomena of life can be most comprehensively, economically and adequately
explained", as Lawson-Tancred puts it [Introduction to De Anima, p.
48]. He praises Aristotle for developing
his 'entelechist' view which avoids Platonic dualism without collapsing into a reductive materialism. Much
recent discussion centres on the alleged similarities between this theory and
functionalism and various other 'holistic' accounts of the 'mind'. But these remain controversial; and
Lawson-Tancred argues that Aristotle's account is sui generis.
(5) Ethics and political philosophy. Aristotle's doctrine of the mean, while prima facie eminently
workable, sometimes seems contrived when applied to particular situations. Many philosophers would go further and reject
his eudaimonistic and teleological ethics, either because they start from a
different position (for example, a deontological, or a utilitarian one), or
because they regard his moral philosophy as unduly intellectual and 'elitist'. It is arguable also that Aristotle's
psychological analysis of weakness of will (akrasia), although more
penetrating and extensive than Plato's, in the last analysis fails to provide
an adequate explanation.
(6) Aesthetics. Aristotle's
account seems to be more positive than Plato's. It can be objected, however, that his concentration on imitation of
'nature' as the aim and criterion of good art ignores such factors as form
(that is, the structure of a work of art) and the role of the imagination in
the creative process.
. Needless to say, all these criticisms and qualifications are
contentious, and in any case can in no way detract from the greatness of
Aristotle as a thinker. His philosophy
was of central importance throughout the Middle Ages, particularly from the
twelfth century onwards when Latin translations of apparently lost works became
available in the West. His emphasis on
detailed analysis of everyday discourse found more than an echo in mid-twentieth
century Oxford. And much of his technical
work is proving to be still fresh, relevant, and challenging to modern scholars
— in relation to such issues as sense and reference, essences and natural
kinds, necessity, causality and explanation, and the nature of the mind.
Aristotle: Your reading should include the Categories, Prior and Posterior Analytics, On Interpretation, Physics, Metaphysics, On the Soul, Ethics, and Poetics. There are Penguin editions of many of these
in English. The most comprehensive
collection is that of J. Barnes, The Complete Works of Aristotle. Perhaps more convenient is A New Aristotle Reader, trans. & ed. J. L. Ackrill,
or The Basic Works of Aristotle,
trans. & ed. R. McKeon. See also the
edition of De Anima by H.
Lawson-Tancred, which contains an excellent introduction. There is also a :oeb edition in 23 volumes.
Studies:
Introductory
J. Barnes, Aristotle.
D. J. Allen, The Philosophy of Aristotle.
Advanced
D. Graham, Aristotle's Two Systems.
T. H. Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles.
J. Lear, Aristotle: The Desire to Understand.
W. D. Ross, Aristotle.
Collections of essays
J. Barnes (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle
J. Barnes, R. Sorabji, and M. Schofield (eds), Articles
on Aristotle.
J. M. E. Moravcsik (ed.), Aristotle.
CONNECTIONS
Aristotle
Note: also the general rejection of Aristotelian
metaphysics and epistemology by the sceptics Pyrrho and Sextus;
by Francis
Bacon (though he continued to utilize much of Aristotle's technical
terminology and indeed acknowledged that there were some positive features in
Aristotelianism); and by Hobbes.
[7c] |
Formal similarities in the (independent) sciences
but no ultimate common single explanatory principle |
Plato→
→Descartes
Comte |
[4a]
[1d]
[2b] |
[10d 11a; cf. 9c] |
Purpose
and function (teleology)
man and Nature; freedom
of will; actions purposive, individuals have
control over actions |
→Posidonius
→Aquinas
→Brentano
Bradley |
[1g]
[4a]
[4b]
[7a] |
[11b] |
'Levels'/ types
of explanation;
compatibility of? mechanism and
teleology |
→Leibniz
Schelling |
[4a]
[1c] |
|
Universals see Knowledge |
[13f 7a] |
Forms
not numbers; mathematical objects immaterial &
unchangeable but
inseparable from matter |
Plato→
→Plotinus |
[1d]
[1g n] |
[21a; see also 19b] |
Virtue acquisition and character
formation: 'corresponsibility' of choices and
nature; can not be taught
directly |
Socrates→
Plato→
→Aquinas
→Dewey
→Ricoeur |
[2b 2d]
[11a b g]
[8b]
[3a]
[5e 10g] |