WITTGENSTEIN
(1889 1951)
ANALYTICAL
PHILOSOPHY
1.
SYSTEMATIC; 2. 'ORDINARY LANGUAGE'
Ludwig Wittgenstein was born in Vienna the
youngest child of a large family. His
father, an industrialist, was a Lutheran, but Ludwig was brought up in his
mother's Roman Catholicism (though he was to disassociate himself from the
Church as an adult). The family home was a centre of musical life (his brother
Paul was the famous pianist). He was
educated firstly at home and then in Linz before studying mechanical
engineering at the Charlottenburg Polytechnic in Berlin. From 1908-11 he carried out research in
aeronautics at Manchester University. Having become interested in philosophy he went to Cambridge to study
with Russell at Trinity College until the outbreak of the First World War.
While serving in the Austrian army he worked on notes which led to the
publication of his Tractatus in 1921. From 1920 to 1926 he worked as a primary
school teacher in Austria having decided that there were no more
philosophical problems to be solved. But
in 1929 he returned to philosophy with renewed energy, and having been awarded
the Cambridge doctorate for his Tractatus he accepted a lectureship there in 1930. He remained at Cambridge until
1941 (apart from a year living in a hut in Norway to work on his Philosophical Investigations), by which time he had succeeded Moore
as professor. During the World War II he
worked as a hospital porter and as a laboratory assistant before returning to
Cambridge in 1944. From 1947 to 1949 he lived in isolation in Ireland.
PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE/ KNOWLEDGE
[1] In his early work [Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus] the period of his logical atomism
Wittgenstein supposed language to consist of propositions (Sätze),
which are the means whereby assertions about the world are made, or through
which thoughts about the world are expressed. [See 3.1 ff.] In its 'projective relation to the world' a
proposition is called the 'propositional sign' and is a 'fact'. Wittgenstein says that the elements of a
propositional sign correspond to the objects of thoughts. Propositions are made up of complex expressions for which we
can substitute descriptions. Ideally
such propositions can be
analysed, broken down ultimately into elementary propositions consisting of
'simple signs', that is, (logically
proper) names. Names stand for simple
things in the world objects. However, he gave no examples of
elementary propositions, or of names, or of what things might be simple
objects; and he remained agnostic about achieving this. Objects may be related to or connected to
other objects. Such possible connections
are called states-of-affairs (Sachverhalte)
[TLP 2]. If the possible connections are actualized, they are facts in the
strict sense (Tatsachen) and are then said to be true (but
otherwise false). Propositions, Wittgenstein says,
are related to the states-of-affairs in that the propositions are 'pictures' (Bilder which means also 'images'
or 'models') [2.1-2.225] rather as toy cars can be arranged on a table to
illustrate a road accident. There is thus a kind of
correspondence or isomorphism between the names and the objects they stand for [a]. Logical constants in elementary propositions ('all', 'some',
'is', 'not', for example) do not, however, belong to pictures and do not denote
[4.0312]. Moreover, although
Wittgenstein supposed all genuine propositions to represent states-of-affairs
in this way, he held that the picturing could be shown only after the analysis
of the complex propositions into elementary propositions.
Because propositions
picture, Wittgenstein supposed they must have something in common with the
states-of-affairs they represent. What
a picture has in common with what it
pictures he calls the 'logico-pictorial form' [2.161-2.17]. Furthermore, in so far as all propositions
are pictures they must have something minimally in common with the reality they
all picture: this is the logical form or
'form of reality' [2.18]. The difference
that makes a picture different from that which it pictures is the
'representational form' [2.173-4]. Naturally neither the pictorial form nor the form of reality can themselves be pictured. Rather they are preconditions for
picturing. Wittgenstein maintains also
that logical form, as
mirrored in language cannot itself be expressed by means of language [b]. They cannot represent
what they must have in common with reality in order to be able to represent it,
that is, logical form; to do so we should have to stand with our propositions
outside logic [4.12]. Propositions show the logical form of reality
[4.121]. They are also manifestations of thoughts, that is, a thought is a
'psychical' correlate of propositions and is thus itself a logical picture of
facts [3 ff.]. While names refer or denote objects, they do not have a sense in themselves but only in the context of propositions [3.1 ff.]. To
understand a name is to understand its reference. Propositions, by contrast, have a sense, in that we understand them as
being related to the 'world' as picturing it (this is not strictly
'reference') [4.021]. "To
understand a proposition means to know what is the case, if it is true"
[4.024]. Wittgenstein thus holds the view that the meaning of a proposition is determined by its
truth-conditions [c], that is, the
conditions under which it is true. And this sense is made clear to us in so far
as we should be able to see the constituent and interrelated names if the
propositions were analysed into elementary propositions.
Whether or not analysis of genuine complex
propositions into elementary ones is possible in practice, Wittgenstein said the relationship between
propositions is truth-functional; and he invented the technique of
truth-functional matrices to exhibit the possible relationships [see 5
ff.]. Thus the truth of the conjunction
'p ∙ q' depends on the truth values of the propositional variables 'p' and 'q': 'p ∙ q' is true if and only if both p
and q are separately true, and false if either p or q is false. Wittgenstein identified two limiting cases: (1) when a proposition is true for all possible combinations of the
elementary propositions; (2) when a proposition is always false for all such combinations. Propositions of the first kind are called tautologies, those of
the second contradictories [4.46 ff.] [d]. Both types are not strictly genuine propositions. Tautologies, which include all propositions
and truths of logic, express no thoughts and say nothing about the world. Neither do they have meaning, that is, sense (Sinn): but they are not nonsensical, because they
have a function, namely, to show us the logical structure of language and thus
possibilities in the world. They also
possess necessity, in contrast to genuine propositions which are contingent and
relate to a world which is 'accidental'. Thus 'Either it is raining or it is not raining' is necessarily true but
of itself it gives us no facts; it only sets out the limits of the
possible. If contingently it is raining
in the world, then the disjunct 'It is
not raining' is not actualized. As for mathematical propositions
these too, Wittgenstein argued, are 'senseless' but not nonsensical. However, they are not tautologies. He supposed them to be equations which
sanction us to substitute one expression for another, and he also regarded them
as necessary, in some sense imposed on us. But while they thereby show us something
about the world they do not 'picture' it. In his later Philosophische
Bermerkungen he adopted a
'constructivist' view [e], arguing that
mathematical propositions are 'made' not discovered.
[2] After Wittgenstein returned to
philosophy in 1929 he gradually came to criticize and eventually reject totally
the doctrines implicit in the Logical Atomism of the Tractatus. In his notebooks
[Blue and Brown Books] and especially
his posthumously published Philosophical
Investigations he attacked the view that words stand for
objects or essences in some rigid or invariable sense [PI I, 1; Brown Book, paras 1
& 2]. So how do words 'mean', have
significance? Take the word 'game' [PI I, 69 ff; Brown Book secs 1 ff.]. There is no single entity or essence denoted by the word, which is a
unique characteristic of all games; and to search for one is futile. In some games a ball is used, in others
cards. Most games are competitive, in
others players play on their own (or perhaps they compete with themselves?).
Rather, we should talk of "family
resemblances", an "over-lapping and criss-crossing" of characteristics and
relationships. His approach is thus now intrinsically
'holistic': 'meaning' is implicit in
these relationships between words and in the ways they are used, not in
any kind of referencing or representing function. Furthermore the activity of pointing as the
basis of 'ostensive definition' is unreliable [Blue Book, pp 1-2; PI I,
27-35]. What is it we may be supposed to
be pointing at the table, its brown colour, its surface? Likewise, in asking what the 'meaning' of a
word is, or the 'real form' of a proposition, or how we understand a language
or 'know' something, we are liable to commit the same error of supposing that there is some entity
an object in the world, an essence, or a mental 'process' or 'entity' named
by the word. To use a word is to
participate in a 'language game' [for example, PI I, 7, and 21 ff.] [a]. Suppose a builder calls out to his
assistant 'slab', 'beam', and the like, while pointing at some object. The assistant responds by fetching the
appropriate material. The words have functions in this 'game'. The language game 'played' by the builder and
his assistant is of course primitive and simple. So, as against his view in the Tractatus, Wittgenstein now argued that there is a multitude of language games corresponding to
different 'forms of life'; there is not just one universal form of language.
That is why he rejected his earlier idea of ultimate simples denoted by basic
elements in our language. What we regard
as ultimate or basic is relative to the language game being played. However, he eschews any attempt to produce a systematic and
definitive categorization of language (in terms of, for example, assertions,
imperatives, and so on). (Implicit here
is a rejection, or at least ignoring of any Fregean 'sense'/ 'force'
distinction) [see, for example, PI I, 22-24] [b]. So how does language 'work'? A language, Wittgenstein says, uses rules which are either implicit or
explicit. They are to be understood in a
wider sense than formal rules of grammar. Such rules guide correct usage of names in a given language game. And in so far as the game is 'public',
that is, played by others in a social context, the rules guarantee that I am
using words correctly, including those that purport to refer to 'private'
experiences (sensations, images, volitions and so on). Indeed, there can be no such
thing as a purely private language to refer to such 'private' or 'inner' mental
experiences. The correct use of
'psychological' words referring to sensations, impressions, pains, beliefs,
'meanings', understanding in general cannot be determined by any kind of
introspection process; for there is no method by means of which we can
compare our usage with new experiences so as to ascertain that names are being
used correctly. Similar considerations apply to the question of
whether we can have thoughts without a language [c]. We do not have to 'look within', as it were,
but rather need only look at the different situations in which the word
'thinking' is used. We shall then find
that it is a mistake to suppose there is a single 'inner' activity called
thought which must precede and be 'translated' into our language. As he writes:
One
might say 'Thinking is an incorporeal process', however, if one were using this
to distinguish the grammar of the word 'I think' from that of, say, the word
'to eat'. Only that makes the difference
between the meanings look too slight. (It is like saying: numerals are actual, and
numbers are non-actual, objects.) An
unsuitable type of expression is a sure means of remaining in a state of
confusion. It as it were bars the way
out. [PI I, 339].
I come to learn how to use psychological words
correctly in the context of a 'public' language-game. For example, it was when I hurt myself as a
child that I first learned from others how to use the sentence 'I am in
pain'. Indeed, according to
Wittgenstein, this can be seen as an aspect of pain behaviour. I do not have to appeal to any private state
of being in pain. Moreover, the sentence
'I know I am in pain' makes no sense at all. I can know that others are in pain by observing their behaviour or because
they tell me they are. But clearly I do
not ask myself whether I am in
pain. Already in the 1930s [Lectures]
Wittgenstein had distinguished between different usages of 'I'. The pronoun has different
functions in 'I have a toothache' and 'I have a bad tooth'. In the latter it can be replaced by 'my
body', but in the latter case the 'I' has no reference it does not denote a
possessor or 'Ego' [d]. As
for proper names,
Wittgenstein now thinks of them as being defined in terms of a loose
association with various descriptions their sense changing accordingly [e]: a name is thus used without a fixed meaning [PI 79]. By the time he had written the Investigations Wittgenstein had also altered
his view of the necessity of the
propositions of mathematics and
logic. These are now seen to be
necessary in virtue of the (non-compulsory) acceptance of rules embedded in the
relevant language 'game' [f]. It follows that because we set our own
standards of consistency we can change the rules if we so wish provided we
are willing to accept the possibly chaotic consequences for our mathematical
discourse as a whole.
In his last years Wittgenstein made some
important contributions to epistemology. [See On Certainty.] His central
thesis is that scepticism,
doubting makes sense only in the context of the foundational 'inherited
background' which constitutes our 'world-picture' and against which we
distinguish between true and false [OC 94, 411] [g]. This picture, articulated
in our language-games, includes such propositions as 'I know I have a brain'
[4], 'The earth has existed for many years past' [411], and 'I know I am in
pain' [504]. This last means nothing;
certainly there is no inner state to which one can appeal [356]. Such propositions constitute a total system
in which all testing, confirmation and disconfirmation of a hypothesis takes
place: "The system is not so much the
point of departure, as the element in which arguments have their life"
[105]. Wittgenstein allows that a proposition such as 'This is a
chair' has the same epistemological status as '2 x 2 = 4', but again he says it
is senseless to talk of knowing them if they are taken out of context and if per
contra it is possible to doubt them [455, 651]. The only special status they can be accorded
is as being part of the 'background'. We cannot appeal to empirical
propositions to prove the existence of the external world [h]. The
existence of the earth, he says [209] is part of the whole picture which forms
the starting-point of belief for him.
Similar considerations apply to claims to universal doubt (even if
hyberbolic). We can make
mistakes, but to seek to doubt everything is crazy [for example, 71, 196, 217], and indeed is self-refuting,
because to do so we would first have to understand the meaning of the sentences
we employ to express our doubt, and "...a language-game is only possible if one trusts something" [509]. Clearly we cannot consistently doubt the language we use [i].
METAPHYSICS/ ETHICS
[3] For Wittgenstein in his Tractatus period 'metaphysical' and ethical propositions, and
indeed all 'non-scientific' propositions can have no sense. (In his later Philosophische Bermerkungen, he
said that "the sense of a question is the mode of its answering" [66-7].) According to him most philosophical problems arise only because we
insist on regarding such propositions as factual. Strictly speaking, they are not propositions
at all. He says we do not understand the
logic of our language [4.003]. As a
result we sometimes attempt to transcend the boundaries of language (as when we
try to talk about the relation between language and the world). Or we do not recognise that the grammatical form of our propositions often
fails to reflect their logical form. The apparent logical form of a proposition
need not be its real one. All philosophy
is a 'critique of language' [4.0031]. However, it is not
a systematic 'science' [4.111] [a]. Its task is to make our thoughts clear
[4.112]. Yet, in its assumptions, stance, and content the Tractatus is in its own
way a 'metaphysical' text perhaps in
the way that Kant's first Critique is. Essentially it is about the nature and limits
of language and the relationship between thought and the world. Its metaphysics is thus implicit in and
coextensive with his logical atomism. What 'traditional' metaphysics
is supposedly 'about', however, lies beyond language and the world [5.633]. Moreover, because
everything in the world is accidental, there can be no value in it; a thing's
value would have to be necessary. Both the subject or 'ego', in
relation to which good and evil exist, and the realm of value are said to be
'transcendental'. The subject,
Wittgenstein says, is a 'limit' of the world [5.632] [b]. All these things which we can say nothing
about may be supposed to exist. We still
think about their possibility when we contemplate the world itself as existing
and as a limited whole. This
Wittgenstein calls 'the mystical'
[6.45]. But even to say that such things exist is a nonsensical proposition;
and this must be "thrown away" like a ladder once one has climbed to the top
[6.54]. If we cannot speak about it, we
must be silent.
In his later philosophy the problem has
shifted. We are no longer concerned with
the world as a limited whole beyond which there is a realm of the
unsayable. What we may say now is relative to the language game we
are playing. Perhaps there are
'metaphysical', ethical, aesthetic, religious language games, with their own
rules and criteria for use. (Arguably implicit here is also the requirement that a clear demarcation be made
between the methods of the natural
sciences and those appropriate to the social sciences a view which was
developed by 'neo-Wittgensteinian' philosophers.) Wittgenstein in fact talks of different 'forms of life' [PI I, 23]. But what can their
purpose be? What can they tell us? To suppose metaphysical or ethical words, for example, are scientific
would be to pull them out of their proper context to misapply the appropriate
rules. If we did this we would be moving
beyond the 'limits' of the language game [c]. If you want to play your own game, so be
it: but what you are doing can be
properly understood only from within by the players themselves. They cannot be
judged by criteria appropriate to a different game. Thus, although Wittgenstein
could not empathize with people who engaged in metaphysical speculation or
participated in religious forms of life, it would seem that, as in his Tractatus period, he wished to protect
those realms including perhaps speculative philosophy itself, from the
predations of positivistically minded philosophers and scientists. Philosophy in a strict sense, however, has now taken on a role akin to
that of therapy. Its function is to
prevent us from going astray in our reasonings by bringing us back to the way
that language actually used in its 'ordinary', that is, proper and appropriate
context [d]. Philosophical
puzzles can be solved if we discover how they arose in the first place:
When
philosophers use a word 'knowledge', 'being', 'object', 'I', 'proposition', 'name' and try to grasp the essence of
the thing, one must always ask oneself is the word ever actually used in this way
in the language which is its original home? What we do is to bring words back
from their metaphysical to their everyday use. [PI I, 116]
We must,
he says gnomically [I, 309], "show the fly the way out of the fly-bottle".
CRITICAL SUMMARY
It is generally accepted that Wittgenstein
created two philosophies. In the first,
which received its definitive expression in the Tractatus, he set out to
present logical propositions as a set of necessary tautologies which reveal the
structure of language and thereby the world. Propositions have meaning by virtue of their contingent 'picturing' of
facts in the world as actualized possible connections or
'states-of-affairs'. Names as constituents
of elementary propositions thus stand in an isomorphic relationship to the
simple objects in the world which they denote. It is in the context of this thesis that he presented his account of
truth-functions.
Most of the objections which can be
brought against his logical atomism were later made by Wittgenstein himself. The main problems relate to the following.
(1) Language was conceived as having but one
function: to picture the world and
thereby communicate facts. However,
there are difficulties with the concept of isomorphic picturing. If we say 'The cat is on the mat', are we
supposing there are three separate factual elements in the world corresponding
to three constituents of the one proposition? Might formulations in different languages entail alternative
correspondences? Wittgenstein was also
faced with the problem of assessing the status of the propositions of the Tractatus itself. His view that they were 'boundary statements'
neither tautologies nor factual propositions is questionable; for in his
later writings philosophy ceased to be an activity of analysing structures to
draw attention to the limits of what can and cannot be said. It becomes instead an empirical study of the
many different functions a language may perform. One's attitude to this second philosophical
approach must clearly depend on one's standpoint. Those in the logical positivist or empiricist
tradition would object to Wittgenstein's criticisms of attempts to assimilate
other modes of discourse to the scientific, and to his move away from the view
that philosophy should seek to eliminate errors by uncovering the formal
logical structures supposedly underlying our 'ordinary' informal
discourse. Even the 'systematic'
philosophers in the analytic tradition are generally not in sympathy with his
informal methods.
(2) Propositions were supposed to have meaning by
virtue of their 'picturing'. Against this Wittgenstein now says that rather
than looking for 'meanings' we should examine the ways language works and how
it is used. Philosophical problems arise
because we fail to remain within the boundaries of a particular mode of
discourse, as when, for example, we treat sensations as if they were material
objects. However, many critics would
argue that we need to have some concept of meaning (perhaps intentional or 'in
the mind') before we can know how to
use language correctly. And they would say that use can relate to private rules
which do not require public validation.
(3) Wittgenstein claimed to have found the way to
eliminate philosophical mystery and error. His critics would say that in so far as his species of linguistic
philosophy "leaves things as they are"
it is not very illuminating or progressive. However, he was not opposed to any modification of conceptual structures
or to the introduction of novel criteria for usage. His
objection was to using terms belonging to a particular mode of discourse as if
different criteria were already applicable. Nevertheless it is still a matter for debate as to whether philosophical
problems can be so readily eliminated in this way.
We have talked of Wittgenstein's 'two'
philosophies. However, it is important
to appreciate the continuities as well as the differences between his
positions. In both periods he was
concerned with the nature and function of language, and with the nature, origin,
and elimination of philosophical puzzles. In both periods too he was interested
in 'boundaries', though in the Tractatus his
concern was with the boundary between
language in general and the 'world', whereas in his later work the boundaries
lie between different modes of discourse. The possibility of a variety of modes of discourse grounded in different
'forms of life' does of course give rise to critical issues concerning an
alleged 'relativism' in his philosophy, which does not allow for any absolute
standpoint for judging, or for a 'pragmatism' according to which any mode of
discourse may be introduced if deemed to be in some sense 'useful'.
Wittgenstein: [of many works] Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus (1921); Lectures (G. E. Moore, 'Wittgenstein's
Lectures in 1930-33'); The 'Blue and Brown' Books (1933-4); Philosophische
Untersuchungen (1958) (Philosophical Investigations); On
Certainty (1949-51).
Studies:
Introductions
A. Grayling, Wittgenstein.
D. Pears, Wittgenstein.
More advanced
M. Addis, Wittgenstein: A Guide for the Perplexed.
D. Bolton, An
Approach to Wittgenstein's Philosophy.
R. J. Fogelin, Wittgenstein.
P. M. S. Hacker, Insight and Illusion.
A. Kenny, Wittgenstein.
Collections of essays
G. Pitcher (ed.), Wittgenstein: The Philosophical Investigations.
H. D. Sluga and D.
Stern (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein.
CONNECTIONS
Wittgenstein