MOORE
(1873 1958)
REALISM/ ANALYTICAL
PHILOSOPHY
George Moore was born
in Upper Norwood, London. His father was
a medical doctor, his mother came from a Quaker merchant family. He was educated at Dulwich College and
Trinity College, Cambridge, where he studied classics and philosophy. He graduated in 1896, and in 1898 was elected
Fellow of Trinity for six years, during which time he engaged in frequent
discussions with Russell. In 1911 he was
appointed university lecturer at Cambridge and in 1925 professor of mental
philosophy and logic. He remained
actively engaged in writing and discussion from his retirement in 1939 until
his death. He was appointed to the Order
of Merit in 1951.
LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS
[1] Although influenced initially by such
theories, Moore came to
reject the doctrines of internal relations and 'psychologism'. And he also disagreed that material
implication means the same as formal implication [a]. He subscribed to an objectivist theory of a
plurality of real universal concepts which are separable from our mental
acts and are the objects of our judgements [see 'The Nature of
Judgement']. They are what 'material things', propositions,
facts, 'complexes, numbers, and minds are made up of. Propositions are relations between the real
concepts; and indeed he seems to identify propositions with things and
'complex conceptions'. He also
distinguishes between empirical
universals (and thence propositions), which exist through time, and a
priori ones, which do not [b].
Because of the problem of false beliefs
[see sec. 2] Moore subsequently changed his views and decided that there could be no propositions in any 'realist'
sense. And he came to think of the
universe as consisting of two independent categories of entities or things
which have 'being': things that exist,
and things which do not exist but 'are' [see 'The Refutation of Idealism']. (He thus rejected the view that there are degrees of
reality. The former category covers particulars (material things, sense-data, mental acts, spatial volumes, and instants of
time); while the latter is
made up of facts and universals (relations, relational properties, and
others which do not involve relations, such as numbers, and qualities such as
good, and perhaps colour). Things that
do not have any being at all are imaginary objects, describable by incomplete
symbols, whereas things
which do have being can be referred to by proper names [c]. What is or is not imaginary and therefore non-denoting, however,
depends on the context in which the relevant statement containing the symbol is
made. The phrase 'the king of
France' in 'the king of France is wise, for example, would not have been an
incomplete symbol if asserted in 1700. Implicit in this approach is a commitment to a form of philosophical analysis [d]; and although Moore repudiated this
description of his methods, he did argue that philosophers differ from each
other in the kinds of analysis they employ ['The Nature and Reality of Objects
of Perception']. In general Moore's mode
of analysis consists in describing concepts by other concepts and often in ways
such that references to the original concepts are eliminated (as 'brother' is
analysed as 'male sibling', for example). [See Moore's reply to Langford in Schillp.] Likewise in his treatment of free will [Ethics, ch. VI] he argues that it is certain that, if we had we
so chosen, we often could (in some sense) have done what we did not
do; and that this sense is such that
'should' can be substituted for 'could'. By implication [according to Austin] 'if'-clauses state the causal conditions [e] on which any different course of action
would have followed.
KNOWLEDGE
[2] In his lectures of 1910-11 [Some Main Problems of Philosophy, ch. 6]
Moore had regarded propositions (or complexes of things) as objects of belief
not beliefs themselves. Some
propositions are true (they are 'facts'), some false, truth being something we can directly 'intuit'.
Knowledge is thus our awareness of propositions, while perception is knowledge
of existential propositions [a]. How then do we account for false
beliefs? There must be false
propositions, Moore said; they are the objects of false beliefs. But when we have a false belief we believe
'what is not', so there cannot be an object. He therefore
concluded not only that there were no false propositions but also that there
were no true ones either. Nevertheless in later lectures of the 1910-11 series [ibid., chs 13-16] he maintained that when we believe something to be
true its truth must consist in its correspondence to a fact [b].
In
his 'Refutation of Idealism' Moore undertook a thorough critique of idealism, which he supposed to
be epitomized primarily by Berkeley's 'esse
est percipi' (though he seemed also to include 'being thought' as an aspect
of 'being perceived'). Moore wanted to
separate the concept of being from that of being perceived; they are neither
identical nor connected in an 'organic unity'. He thus
distinguished between an act of consciousness and the actual object. This act
of consciousness, however, is also an act of cognition: to have an idea
or sensation is to know, that is, be
aware of something outside, which is not now a proposition but may be a
physical object [c]. Later ['Nature and Reality of Objects of
Perception'] Moore argued that the term 'sensation' is ambiguous. The actual 'content' of, say, a
seeing experience (he uses the term 'sense-datum'
to refer to this content) may cease to exist, in which case the seeing itself
also ceases. But what is experienced
(the physical object we ordinarily believe we directly perceive) may continue
to exist [d].
Knowledge in a general sense, for Moore,
consists in a relationship. He
firstly distinguishes between knowledge by direct apprehension (acquaintance) and knowledge by
indirect apprehension. A typical example of the former is the
relationship between the consciousness of a perceiver and, say, a patch of
colour. Memory experiences illustrate
the latter as when we remember seeing an object but neither it nor the
associated sense-data are present to our consciousness. Knowledge in a 'proper' sense is now defined as involving (1) a complex
relation between an act of consciousness and a direct apprehension of a
proposition; provided (2) the proposition is true, we believe it to be true,
and there are grounds for our belief (though Moore does not say what
these might be). If the proposition is
known to be true directly without further support, this form of 'proper'
knowledge is called immediate. Moore also refers to what we might call
latent knowledge, that is, knowledge we
have in one of the previous senses but where there is nothing we are actually
conscious of at the moment (for example, that 12 x 3 = 36). But in general he is critical of any distinction between 'acquaintance' and 'description'. Knowledge by acquaintance, he says, is
neither knolwledge nor acquaintance [Some
Main Problems of Philosophy].
The kinds of things that, according to
Moore, we may be supposed to know include not only material objects but also acts of consciousness,
sense-data, universals, matters of fact, synthetic necessary truths, and
'entities' such as 'the good' [e]. But his account of knowledge
raises two problems. (1) How can we be sure of our knowledge of these various things? To answer this Moore
generally invokes commonsense
or 'ordinary' belief ['A Defence of Common Sense' and 'Proof of an
External World']. We can
appeal to facts and point to objects. There are also other people we can communicate with [f]. Thus he is broadly empiricist, though it is clear that 'experience' for him includes much more than
what we gain through the senses. (2) In perception, how should we describe sense-data and account for
the relationship between them and (a) universals, and (b) physical objects? As to the nature of a sense-datum, what we
immediately perceive, Moore says, is not part of the surface of an object, nor
is it the appearance of such a part. Still less is it the name of a set of actual or possible
sensations. Rather we must suppose a sense-datum is some sort of
object that exists only when we are perceiving it. Indeed different people have different and
often inconsistent sense-data. He
concludes that a visual sense-datum is a patch of colour which, as a
particular, relates to the colour itself, colour being a non-relational
universal. As for the relationship between sense-data and material
objects, Moore oscillated between a logical constructivist or phenomenalist
theory and a version of representationalism [g],
both of which raise difficulties concerning our knowledge of physical objects.;
and he was never really satisfed with either. He suggested later that these problems might be dealt with by means of
inductive or analogical arguments.
ETHICS
[3] [See especially Principia Ethica.] Moore rejects any
attempt to define 'the good' in terms of some natural quality, or indeed in
terms of any quality at all. To try to do so is to commit what he calls 'the naturalistic fallacy'. If, for example, we define good as pleasure, then when we say
'pleasure is good' we are saying no more than 'pleasure is pleasure'. Good, for Moore, is essentially indefinable and unanalysable; it is a
non-natural entity which we can 'intuit' in things. At best, all we can do is to see how 'good'
relates to other value terms to determine its meaning by engaging in a kind of
descriptive language analysis [a]. What kinds of things can be said to be good? Moore's account is 'organicist', that is, he
thinks of the goods man aspires to as unities whose goodness is more than just
a mechanical sum of their
parts. And of such goods he singles out
friendship and appreciation of beauty. To determine this he imagines each whole to be the only thing existing
in the universe and then considers whether it would be better if it existed
than if it did not.
Ethics is also concerned with rights, duties, and virtues; and each of
these concepts, Moore says, is definable
in terms of goodness. To determine the
rightness of an action, how we ought to behave in a given situation, or what
being virtuous consists in, therefore requires a consideration of the causal
consequences how much good is produced, whether it is the greatest
amount as compared with what alternative actions might bring about. (This is not the same as saying that an
action is morally obligatory if the actual performing of it makes the universe
better than if one were to perform a different action [see Ethics].) However, he
recognised that any assessment of consequences is not an easy task and that
that following the
conventional rules (rights and duties) of society is best calculated to maximize
the good [b].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Moore's arguments in his
metaphysics and theories of knowledge are generally inconclusive. But they do illustrate the importance for him
of careful examination of the meanings of words, in both their 'ordinary' and
philosophical contexts though as a means of achieving clarification rather
than to show that the relevant philosophical problems are in any way
spurious. Nevertheless, for all their
supposed simplicity his conclusions are not immune to criticism; and there are
many assumptions and unanswered questions. The following issues are particularly important:
(1) What is the basis or justification for the distinction between the
'act of consciousness' and its objects?
(2) The relationship of sense-data to physical or material objects and
to universals needs to be clarified. What are sense-data (e.g., a patch of colour)? Are they particulars or
universals? Moore says they exist only
when we are perceiving them. They do not belong to the surface of objects. But is it not physical objects that we perceive? How then do sense-data relate to
objects? Moore does not seem to offer
any definitive conclusions on these matters. Likewise, in his metaphysics we are left with a multitude of 'entities',
which are not to the taste of many recent philosophers, any more than is his
distinction between 'exist' and 'are'.
(3) As for his ethics, it is generally held now that Moore's
'naturalistic fallacy' is less devastating than has often been supposed in the
past. There is no objection to defining
good stipulatively in terms of, say, pleasure (though this may not be a
fruitful approach to human behaviour). In any case, if there is a fallacy, it consists in the attempt to define
good (a value) in terms of a non-moral quality (fact) rather than being any
inherent inconsistency in ethical naturalism itself. However, against Moore it might be said that
we do in fact define 'good' in different ways and in different contexts, as a
qualification of some object (good book, good person, good mark, and so
on). Another objection is that Moore has
a limited view of ethical qualities. There are also the standard difficulties with his utilitarianism. Should consequences be used as the criterion
of morality? Are consequences
quantifiable, measurable? It is arguable
also that Moore's conventionalism does not cope adequately with moral
conflicts.
Moore: 'The Nature of Judgement'
(1899); Principia Ethica (1903); Some Main Problems of Philosophy (lectures, 1910/11); Ethics (1912); Philosophical
Studies [including 'The Refutation of Idealism' (1903) and 'The Nature and
Reality of Objects of Perception' (1905)]; and Philosophical Papers.
Studies
A. J.
Ayer, Russell and Moore.
T. Baldwin, G. E. Moore.
A. R. White, Moore, A Critical
Exposition.
Collections
of essays
A. Ambrose and M. Lazerowitz (eds.) G. E. Moore: Essays in
Retrospect
P. A.
Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of G. E.
Moore.
CONNECTIONS
Moore