LOCKE
(1632 1704)
EMPIRICISM
John Locke was born
at Wrington in Somerset, the son of a Puritan attorney. He was educated at Westminster School and
Christ Church, Oxford, where he studied classics and scholastic philosophy. He graduated B.A. in 1656, proceeded to the
M.A. in 1658, and was appointed Student (that is, Fellow) and Tutor in Greek at
Christ Church. He was elected Fellow of
the Royal Society in 1668. He also
studied medicine, though did not take his medical degree until 1675, and he
never practised. Appointed secretary to
Lord Ashley, the Earl of Shaftesbury in 1667, he took an active part in both
the political and intellectual life of the day. He spent some time in France, then in 1683 in Holland, to which he fled
because of his association with the by then discredited Shaftesbury. He was also deprived of his Studentship. While abroad he met many of the chief
thinkers and continued his work on his Essay
Concerning Human Understanding. This
was published in 1690, Locke having returned to England after the revolution of
1688. Further books followed, and he was
also once again active in public life until 1700.
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE
[1] The term 'Idea' is employed in a wide sense to stand
for "whatever is the object of the understanding when a man thinks" [Essay Concerning Human Understanding, I, 1, viii; II, 1, i], and includes
sense-experiences, images, and concepts. These thus
represent or 'signify' things or what the mind constructs from
representations. Ideas, in their turn,
are referred to by words. Words
are to be used as "sensible marks of ideas": "the ideas they
stand for are their proper or immediate signification" [III, 2, i]. Thus Locke seems to hold an 'ideational' version of the
denotation theory of meaning [a]. This 'signification' is,
however, a matter of arbitrary choice or
convention. There are additionally some
words which signify not ideas but "the connection that the mind gives to ideas or propositions" [III, 7, i], for example, 'particles' such as
'is', 'is not', 'but'. Now, many of our ideas can, by a
process of abstraction, become general, that is, they can be made to
represent more than one individual. Words can then become general by being made to signify these general
ideas [III, 3, vi]. Thus 'man' may
signify not just this man but all those individuals who conform to this
abstract idea. Likewise the general term
'triangle' seems to refer to what all triangles have in common. Their different and inconsistent 'parts' have
been abstracted and left out: it must therefore be "neither oblique nor
rectangle, neither equilateral, equicrural, nor scalenon; but all of these and
none at once" [IV, 7, ix]. General names thus stand for
what Locke calls 'nominal essence', that is, the common features a thing we suppose a thing to possess
by virtue of which it is that
thing. However, the 'real' essence of a thing (that is, its
inner constitution, that which makes it the individual thing it is) is unknowable;
and we give it no name. (He rejects
completely the notion of a real fixed essence as that which is common to
members of a species [III, 3, xvii]. ) This is in effect Locke's 'conceptualist' treatment of
the problem of 'universals' [b]. Despite his seemingly confident account,
Locke says that language is in a sense imperfect [III, 9]. The ideal is that a given word will excite
the same idea in different people: but
it is clear that this does not happen in the case of 'complex ideas' and other ideas the mind puts
together. He also discusses [III, 10]
what he supposes to be abuses
of words. These can give rise to error
in a variety of ways [c]. Words
may be misused, as when we employ them without clear ideas, or learn names
before we know the ideas they signify. We may misapply them old words being used with new significations, or
new ones that do not signify (for example, 'matter', which we suppose stands for an idea
signifying something distinct from body and real in nature), or cannot signify
(for example, 'real essence'). (If we assume that Locke in effect accepts a
denotation theory of meaning, such non-signifying words must presumably be
regarded as meaningless.) It is equally
mistaken to suppose that words have "a certain and evident signification". Language being used to convey rapidly our
ideas and thereby the knowledge of things, Locke recognises the seriousness of
the errors misuse of language leads to; and he devotes Bk III, chapter 11 to a
discussion of how they might be avoided.
KNOWLEDGE
[2] In the Essay Locke sets out to discover the origin, certainty, and extent
of human knowledge, and to investigate the "grounds and degrees of belief,
opinion, and assent" [I, 1, ii]. Where
do ideas come from? How do we acquire
them? Can we distinguish between
knowledge and opinion? He starts [1,
2-4] by rejecting all
theories of innate ideas or principles, whether they be of a logical
nature, such as 'it is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be', or
are practical/ moral ones. The argument
from "universal consent" is, he says, worthless. Such agreement can be explained in other
ways. And in any case there is no
genuine universal consent; small children and idiots are unaware of such
principles.
What then is Locke's account of ideas? All our ideas come
from experience, that is, from sensation or from reflection [see
II, 1] [a]. The former is the result of the effect on the mind of external objects,
while the latter is the result of considering the operation of our minds (that
is, through perception, thinking,
doubting, believing, willing) on sensations, through the 'internal sense' [II,
1, iv]. He goes on [throughout Book II]
to distinguish different kinds of ideas. Firstly, ideas are either simple
or complex. Simple ideas [5-11] are received passively and are (1) of sensations colour, taste,
etc. (one sense), or space, figure (two or more senses); (2) of reflection,
such as perception, willing; or (3) of a mixture of sensation and reflection,
for example, pleasure, pain, power, existence, unity. Complex ideas [13 ff.] are divided into types of 'objects': ideas of substances, modes, and relations, all of which result from the
mind's acting on simple ideas. (He also
includes an alternative classification in terms of 'activities': simple ideas
are combined into one complex one; two ideas, simple or complex, can be
compared without being united and can produce relations; ideas can be separated
(abstracted) from others accompanying them to produce general ideas.) How do we account for the origin of our
simple ideas? Locke says that things
possess 'powers' [7] to produce ideas in
our minds; and he calls these powers qualities. Now, qualities are either original or primary, or are secondary [8]. Primary ideas are
those which produce in us simple, ideas of solidity, extension, figure, motion,
rest, and number. Our ideas of primary
qualities actually resemble the bodies possessing them their patterns exist
in the bodies themselves. Our ideas of secondary
qualities, however, (colours, sounds, etc.) do not resemble anything in the
bodies which give rise to them [b].
Complex ideas of substances [23]. We can have clear and distinct
ideas of individual 'substances', that is, corporeal, extended things [c] (for example, the sun), because these are just collections
or combinations of simple ideas. And we
learn to associate the qualities of things. Thus a sound can lead us to think of a colour or shape as belonging to
the idea of a particular thing. But we
also go further, Locke says, when we ask what keeps a collection of ideas
together in a complex. How can they
'subsist'? To answer this we must
suppose there must be a 'substratum' which supports the qualities producing our
ideas. It is this substratum we call substance, the primary
qualities being 'accidents'. This is Locke's idea of substance in general [23] [d].
Clearly we do neither perceive nor have knowledge of such substance: it is but an abstraction and an
inference. In the same way we can arrive
at ideas of a 'spiritual
substance' underpinning our simple ideas of thinking, doubting, perceiving,
etc., and of a Supreme Being. Such ideas, in contrast to those of ideas of particular substances, are
neither clear nor distinct. The mind is conceived by Locke
as consisting in an unknowable 'substratum'; and he believes that we are probably both material
and immaterial substance though this cannot be proved. (We might of course be just material but with
the capacity to think added by God.) [See IV, xxiii, 19.] He also says that there can be no solution to the problem of the
relationship between mind and body [e].
Ideas of relations. [25] Relations
are regarded by Locke as (1) complex
ideas derived from a general activity of reflection on the data of sensation;
(2) the result of a specific
activity, viz, the comparing of two simple or complex ideas [f]. Of particular importance is the relation of causality. [26] We notice, says Locke, that particular things begin to exist. That which produces any simple or complex idea we call the cause; that which is produced is the effect. Thus when wax melts the simple idea of heat
is the cause, the simple idea of fluid is the effect. Similarly the complex idea of wood is the
effect of the complex idea of fire. He
distinguishes between three kinds of production: (1) generation when a new
substance comes from a pre-existent material; (2) alteration when a
pre-existent idea produces in itself a new simple idea; and (3) creation when
something comes into existence from no pre-existent material. The relation of cause and effect is one which obtains between
ideas. Nevertheless, Locke says that it
is grounded in active power possessed by substances to affect each other and to
produce ideas in us [see II, 21]. We get the idea of this power mainly by 'introspecting' and thereby
discovering in ourselves our own capacity to exercise power over our minds and
bodies by volition or willing. (And willing, he says, is to be
distinguished from desire: desire, as a
state of "uneasiness of the mind for
want of some absent good", determines the will [II, 21,
xxx-xxxii].) We can also get an 'obscure
idea' of active power by looking at the way a ball communicates its motion to
another at rest. Although the relation between cause and effect is
discovered through experience, Locke seems to regard the connection as
necessary in that he says that
everything which has a beginning must have a cause [g]. Locke's discussion of relations leads on to
the concepts of identity and diversity. [27] It is clear, he says, that two things apparently alike in all
respects but existing in different places at the same time must have their own
separate identity. To allow for the
possibility of two substances of different kind occupying the same place at a
given time (they would presumably have to be spiritual beings) he says that
existence itself must be the principle of individuation, existence being
"incommunicable" to the two beings. Identity can change, however, if parts of the thing are added or
removed. Furthermore living things
possess an identity in a different way from non-living things, in that, while
in both cases continuous existence in space and time is required, in living
things (vegetables and animals) the fleeting increasing or decreasing particles
of matter are "vitally united" and constitute the continuing organization
appropriate to that thing. The criterion of self-identity is thus bodily continuity. This is the case also with man; and Locke
rejects the possibility that a continuous soul can constitute the criterion, on
the grounds that, given reincarnation, we could never be sure that a particular
living thing was, say, a hog or a man. Nevertheless, consciousness
as the manifestation of an immortal soul substance is the basis for
identification of a man as a person the
self [h]: "a thinking intelligent being, that has
reason and reflection, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking
thing, in different times and places" [II, 27, xii]. Thus separate and distinct consciousnesses
existing at different time in the same body would constitute different persons
for the same man.
Having set out his view as to the origin
of knowledge Locke must now [Book IV] consider what knowledge involves and what
can be known. Knowledge,
he says, consists in "the perception of the connection and agreement, or
disagreement or repugnancy, of any of our ideas" [IV, 1, ii]. He explains this by reference to a number of kinds of agreement
or disagreement:
(1) Identity or diversity. Here the mind recognises, when it has an
idea, that it is what it is and is not another; for example, "Blue is not
yellow".
(2) Relation. The mind perceives a relation between any two
ideas, such as "Two triangles upon equal bases between two parallels are
equal".
(3) Coexistence. In cases of this type the mind recognises
that particular ideas always accompany others in a given complex. Example:
"Iron is susceptible of magnetical impression".
(4) Lastly Locke refers to ideas as corresponding
to a "real existence". "God is" is of
this kind.
(These 'real' connections are to
be contrasted with those connections or associations of ideas [i] which are attributable to chance or
custom many of which, Locke says lead us into error [see II, 33].)
He goes on [IV, 2] to distinguish three degrees of knowledge: (1) We have intuitive knowledge when we perceive an
agreement or disagreement without the intervention of another idea, as,
for example, "White is not black". This
is the paradigm, the clearest and most certain kind of knowledge, he says.
(2) Less clear than intuition is demonstrative knowledge, which requires intervening ideas to perceive agreement or disagreement.
It thus depends on proofs. A typical example is the discovery that three
angle of a triangle are equal to two right angles.
(3) Sensitive knowledge of "particular existence". Thus we suppose ourselves to be aware of the existence of
external objects through our senses (for example, of a rose by its
scent). However, this is the least certain or clear degree of
knowledge; we must recognise the possibility of error. Strictly speaking, we cannot pass beyond what is present to our
senses [j]. Sensitive knowledge apart, whatever falls short of intuition or
demonstration in general truths is said by Locke to be faith or opinion.
What then are the limits of our knowledge,
given these three degrees? [3 -11] Knowledge of identity and diversity extends
as far as the ideas: we perceive them
and their agreement or disagreement intuitively. Knowledge of coexistence is more limited; for
in the collection of ideas we are confined to we can discern no visible
connection between simples making up the complex ideas. Neither can we discover any connection
between any secondary quality and the primary qualities it depends on. As for relations, we cannot easily say how
far our knowledge extends, because we can never be sure there are no more
intermediate ideas to be discovered. Locke also says we
can have intuitive knowledge of our own existence as immaterial substance in so
far as through the very process of doubting other things we perceive that we
are thinking selves, although he denied that its essence consists in its
thinking; we may not always be doing so [k]. Locke rejects the ontological argument for the existence of God [IV, 10, vii; see also King's Life of Locke, ii] on the grounds that the idea of
a necessary existence does not prove that a perfect being actually exists. But
he claims to have demonstrative knowledge, although he says we cannot know
God's essence; we are limited to our complex idea of the infinite being and our
arguments must proceed only by analogy [IV, 16, xii] [l]. Starting from his knowledge of his own existence, he says he
could not have produced himself and that therefore he must have had a beginning
in something which existed eternally and which contains in itself all the
qualities, power, intelligence, etc. we ourselves posses but to an absolute
degree. Other than knowledge of our self
and of God our knowledge must be of the sensitive kind confined to general
experiences of our senses. However, while we may thereby have good
reason in everyday life for supposing external things to exist corresponding to
our sensitive ideas, there is no necessary connection. But Locke nevertheless says that our simple ideas have
'conformity' with the reality of things that produce them which is sufficient
for "real knowledge" [IV, 4, ii-iv] [m]. As for complex ideas, they can
give us real knowledge in mathematics, but this is formal, concerned only with
the properties of ideas or the intuitable relations between them, and says
nothing about the external world [n]. We can also have 'real' knowledge of substances in so far as our ideas of substances are constructed out of simple ideas which
have been found consistently to coexist; but this knowledge is of nominal essences not of
real essences though Locke
supposes they correspond
to 'archetypes' in the external world [o]. All such sensitive and 'real'
knowledge is thus only probable [IV, 15]. The grounds for the truth of a given
proposition about things, substances, etc. are derived from (1) what we may
discover from our own observation and previous experience which has proved to
be consistently regular; and (2) the testimony of others. Locke [IV, 16, v ff.] divides propositions which admit degrees of
probability into (i) verifiable matters
of fact (for example, "It
froze in England the last winter"); and (ii) matters which cannot be empirically verified (for example, heat consists in a violent agitation of its minute burning
parts). In such cases we may appeal to analogy [p] (arguing from our observation that heat
is produced by rubbing two bodies together). Both natural science and history are therefore grounded in propositions
which are only probable. Locke also
notes that identical statements (such as 'An A is an A', and statements in
which a part of any complex idea is predicted of the whole (for example, 'Lead
is a metal'), or is part of the definition of the term defined ('Every man is
an animal or living body') are but 'trifling' propositions which bring no increase to our knowledge [IV, 8] [q].
As for matters of faith
(Locke seems to have been a committed Anglican), he says [IV, 16, xiv] that what is revealed by God is not
probable but certain. Nevertheless, we
must appeal to reason to show that what is claimed to be a revealed truth is in
fact so [r]. Revealed truth, although not discoverable by human reason (without God's
help), must yet not be contrary to it. And Locke is highly critical of those whom he terms 'enthusiasts' who
are convinced of the truth of what they feel simply because of the strength of
their convictions.
ETHICS
UTILITARIANISM
[3] Locke argues [Essay,
Books II and IV] that the
basic rules of morality can be demonstrated and known through reason working on
experience [a]. The ideas which occur in ethical statements,
such as justice and honesty (and which are 'real essences'), are derived from
our own experience: but the statements
themselves, which are made up of relations between the ideas, can be shown to
be true independently of that experience and to be so with clarity and
certainty; for we have real knowledge of them. In Book II he distinguishes
between a general sense of 'good' (we
might call it 'natural' good) and moral good. Good, is that which is "apt to cause or increase pleasure"
(bad or evil conversely producing pain) [II, 20, ii; 21, 42]. Moral good, on the other hand, is "the conformity of our voluntary
actions to some law" [b], as a result of
which we experience our 'reward' according to the law-giver's will. Moral evil correspondingly involves
disagreement with the law-giver and leads to an experience of pain [II, 28,
v]. Locke uses the term 'law' in three
ways [II, 28, vii-xl. There is divine law, which determines an action as a (morally good) duty or
as a (morally evil) sin: God's
will is the "true ground of morality" [I, 3, xii]. Subordinate to this is civil law, by which action is
adjudged to be innocent or criminal. And
lastly an action is virtuous or vicious with respect to the "philosophical" law of opinion. Morality for Locke thus consists in following
rules ultimately laid down by God. How
then are they known? While he seems to accept the possibility of revelation, he
argues that we acquire a
sufficient knowledge of divine law through
"the light of nature", that is, reason... Locke accepts the
concept of a positive 'natural' law and says it cannot be ascertained by the
reason independently of God [c].
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
SOCIAL
CONTRACT THEORY
[4] In his second Treatise on Civil Government Locke
says that man started in a state of nature. This was not, however, a state of war;
because there is a natural law,
discoverable by reason and originating in , which grounds the idea of equality
of all men as rational beings [section 6] [a]. Natural law gives rise to natural
rights. It obliges a man not
to harm another "in his life, health, liberty or possessions" [6].
Correspondingly a man has
a duty and hence a right to self-preservation,
freedom, and to property (which
Locke understands to comprise "life, liberty, and estates", and which he
regards as the basic right
in so far as it contributes to his self-preservation [b]. We possess property by virtue of our labour [c] (clearing
land, sowing seed, building the home, and so on). But Locke stresses that we should acquire
goods only to extent that they are sufficient for his needs. Now, because many men in the state of nature
do not actually respect the rights of others, Locke says that an organized
society should be formed so as to ensure their rights are protected. In forming such a society, that is, joining what he calls a social compact, men give their consent
freely to relinquish a degree of their natural liberty by vesting authority in
a legislative body to make and enforce laws for the common good (as he says, quoting Cicero, "salus populi suprema lex": the welfare of the people is the supreme law
[158] ), and by agreeing to abide by the will of the majority. Their liberties, although more
restricted, will thereby be made more secure [d]; and he argues that all people born
into the society or 'commonwealth' have given at least their tacit consent to their
membership. Locke rejects absolute monarchy as being inconsistent with civil
society [e]. But he also advocates a separation of
powers as between the legislature, executive (including judicial), and
federative functions the latter being concerned with relations of the society
with other states. However, the
legislature remains supreme and cannot be altered by, say, a hereditary ruler
without the consent of the people. If a
government is dissolved as a result of such alteration, or by conquest from
outside, the people have
the right to rebel if they judge the revolution to be justified [f]. (He says also that anyone can always withdraw from the society
if he ceases to accept the compact.)
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Locke is arguably more
'modern' than Descartes, not simply because of the bare chronological fact but
also on account of his more rigorous
rejection of scholastic assumptions (which Descartes, for all his radicalism,
had not discarded), and his acceptance
of Newton's methodology in the natural sciences [a] (as against Descartes' emphasis on deduction and reason). He is noteworthy too for the substantial
contribution he made to a genuine theory of knowledge grounded in
sense-experience and utilizing justification criteria. Nevertheless, there is much in Locke's
philosophy that later thinkers have criticized.
(1) How far Locke should be
regarded as being wedded to a denotation theory of meaning is debatable. If this is his position then it is open to a
double objection: (a) that words have many different uses, and the denotation
theory is too restrictive; (b) that words primarily refer to things rather than
'ideas'. (Locke's usage of the term
'idea' is in any case too wide-ranging.) However, as an 'ideational' variant, his theory may be understood as
emphasizing language as playing a mediational role: my utterances elicit in you similar ideas to
those with which my words are associated... Nevertheless, although he does talk of 'common use', he is still
committed to the view that the ideas (of sense or reflection) supposedly
denoted by words are private to each user; and this gives rise to a problem
concerning communication of shared meanings in the 'public' context. He has also been criticized for holding the
view that general terms denote 'nominal essences' common features abstracted
from a number of different sorts of thing (triangles, for example). On the
credit side, he has been praised for having drawn attention to the various ways
in which the misuse of words leads to error.
(2) In his theory of knowledge
and metaphysics, while firmly empiricist in his account of the derivation of
ideas (he rejects innate ideas in a strong sense), Locke allows for intuitive
and demonstrative knowledge. But it is
doubtful whether this (moderate) rationalist feature of his thought is
consistent with his acceptance of sense-experience as his starting point. More serious problems arise with his acceptance of a rigid
distinction between primary and secondary qualities (the latter being 'powers'
of the former) and their corresponding ideas. Is the distinction tenable at least in the Lockean form? This is clearly relevant to his realist
theory of perception. How can we know
primary qualities 'represent' the world? Even more serious is his assumption that underlying qualities of a thing
is a substance or substrate about which we can know nothing, and which is
endowed with a 'power' to produce in us complex ideas. Is this a 'real' essence or but a collection
of ideas? What is this 'power' (the
paradigm case of which is ourselves as active, willing beings), which grounds
the causal relation between ideas? Whether they actually exist in material entities is questionable. In the last analysis, Locke appeals to
'commonsense' and practical considerations to dismiss scepticism about such
issues.
(3) Locke's theory of the self
and personal identity is original but controversial. We can know nothing of spiritual substance
(he equivocates as to whether it is material or immaterial) except that it
thinks. However, his criterion of
identity that it lies neither in thinking nor in bodily continuity, but in
memory and responsibility poses obvious problems for amnesiacs. It has been suggested also that his
references to 'sameness' of memory involves him in circular reasoning.
(4) Locke's political philosophy arguably marks an
advance on that of Hobbes. His account
of human nature and society is less depressing and more liberal there being
no suggestion of absolutism. But while
one can accept the importance of the preservation of life and liberty, his
emphasis on property as the basis of freedom and a natural right is less
acceptable to many theorists today, especially with reference to such issues as
universal rights and fair distribution of goods. Likewise his attitude to minorities and his
provision for their opting out of the social contract is arguably unrealistic.
The underpinning by God of the natural law also represents an approach
different from Hobbes's. But God might seem to be redundant in Locke's
utilitarian ethics in so far as the
laws which when acted upon produce our 'good' are in principle discoverable
through reflection on experience. However, it is no doubt comforting to find out through the natural light
of reason that God has sanctioned them.
Locke: An Essay Concerning Human Understanding(1689), (ed.) P. H. Nidditch; Two Treatises of Government (1690) there are several editions, for example,
those of E. Barker and P. Laslett.
Studies:
Introductory
J. Dunn, John Locke.
D. J. O'Connor, John Locke.
Advanced
R. I.
Aaron, John Locke.
J.
Bennett, Central Themes: Locke, Berkeley
and Hume .
J. L.
Mackie, Problems from Locke .
J. W. Yolton, Locke and the
Way of Ideas.
Collections
of essays
V. C.
Chappell (ed.), The Cambridge Companion
to Locke.
C. B.
Martin and D. M. Armstrong eds), Locke
and Berkeley: A Collection of Critical
Essays.
I. C.
Tipton (ed.), Locke on Human
Understanding.
CONNECTIONS
Locke
Note: In the following it is assumed that the influence of Plato on Locke
was mediated through the Cambridge Platonists; and any Epicurean influence may
be attributed to his reading of the works of Gassendi (1592-1665). Although Locke was critical of the
Aristotelian scholasticism in which he had been educated at Oxford, he does not
seem to have extricated himself fully from that tradition as is shown by much
of his language and many of his concepts. A number of references to Aquinas are therefore included primarily as
the representative scholastic thinker.
[2f] |
Relations from complex |
→Hume |
[1d] |
[2n] |
Mathematical
propositions
relations of ideas; give no
knowledge of
external world |
Descartes→
→Hume
Kant |
[1d]
[1g 2a]
[1b] |
[2p; cf. 2l] |
Sensitive and real knowledge only probable: matters of fact verifiable through observation or testimony; analogy for non-verifiable |
Epicurus→
→Hume
→Mill |
[1a]
[1g]
[2a] |
[2q] |
Identical propositions are 'trifling' and give no knowledge |
Kant
Mill |
[1a]
[1c] |
[2r] |
Certain knowledge in revelation (reason needed to confirm) |
Aquinas→ |
[1a] |
[4a] |
State of nature not a 'war'; natural law and equality of men as rational beings |
Hobbes→
→Hume
→Rousseau
→Bentham |
[7b]
[4a]
[1a]
[1c] |
[4b] |
Natural rights: self-preservation, freedom, 'property' (includes life and liberty) |
Hobbes→
→Rousseau
→Bentham |
[7c]
[1e]
[1c] |
[4c] |
Property through labour |
Marx |
[2e] |
[4d] |
Social 'compact' between members: authority to legislature only for the common good; natural liberty restricted but more secure |
Cicero→
Hobbes→
→Hume
→Rousseau
→Bentham
→Rawls |
[2f]
[7c d 7f]
[4c]
[1f-h]
[1c 1e]
[1d] |