JAMES
(1842 1910)
'RADICAL
EMPIRICISM'/ PRAGMATISM
William James was
born in New York. His father was a
philosopher and Swedenborgian theologian; his brother was Henry James the
novelist. He was brought up in a liberal
atmosphere, and received a wide education in a number of schools in Europe
before studying medicine at Harvard and experimental physiology under von
Helmholtz at Heidelberg. He gained his
M.D. degree in 1869. From 1873 he
lectured at Harvard, initially in physiology and psychology and then from 1879
in philosophy, in which he had been becoming increasingly interested for a
number of years after an intellectual and emotional crisis. He was appointed full professor of psychology
in 1889 and of philosophy in 1897. He gave the Gifford Lectures at Edinburgh in
1901/2 and the Hibbert Lectures at Oxford in 1908/9.
METHODOLOGY/ KNOWLEDGE
[1] [See Pragmatism.] James's pragmatism
is a procedure for determining the 'meaning' of concepts and theories [a]. We look to the particular practical effects
of an object or theory to achieve clarity in our thoughts about it. If two different theories bring about the
same consequences they are really the same thing. But more importantly his pragmatic method is a theory of truth.
Truth for
James is a property of some of our beliefs expressed in statements, whereby
they relate to things, objects in the world, that is, possible experiences [Lecture VI; also The Meaning of Truth]. The
'correspondence' is accounted for not through any kind of 'picturing' but in terms of the way our ideas
are made true. He thinks of an
idea as a plan of action, producing consequences. The idea, which is the starting-point (terminus a quo), will if it is
true lead to the consequences (the terminus ad quem). Unverified 'truths' are therefore true only
potentially. If a given truth or theory
works, then it must 'mediate', that is, be consistent with previous truths and
the appropriate new experiences. This usually gives a 'satisfaction'
as a sign of truth [b]: but this is not a sufficient condition, for
subsequent evidence may show the idea to be false.
James explains his general philosophical
position [see also Radical Empiricism]
with reference to (1) a 'postulate', (2) a 'statement of fact', and (3) a
'generalized conclusion'. The postulate
is that philosophers
should consider only those matters which are definable in terms of experience;
therein lies the utility of concepts [c]. But what does he mean by 'experience'? Firstly he accepts
the distinction between 'relations of ideas' and 'matters of fact' [d]. With reference to the latter, he distinguishes between 'pure' and 'ordinary'
experience. Pure experience is pure immediate feeling or
sensation before it is categorized through reflection, that is, before
we differentiate between consciousness and content, or mind and matter. As for ordinary (phenomenal) experience, this is of reality as a
plurality ordered by mind and revealed to us through our categorization. Our experience is a unity in a formal or
psychological sense rather than an ontological sense [e]. James is critical of traditional a
priori metaphysics, and of Absolute Idealism in particular. He says that there can be no realizable 'final' or 'absolute' truth,
because all beliefs are open to the possibility of revision. None of them is definite or determinate; they are all inter-dependent and
relative to human experience. He
calls this his 'humanism' [f]. And he also rejects
the doctrine that relations are internal
with its consequence that the world is unreal or only partially real [g]. For him relations are external and real; the concepts they relate are not
changed by their being related in conjunctive or disjunctive judgements. Indeed, such relations are themselves objects
of experience just as 'things' are (this
is his 'statement of fact'); and we can be said to have knowledge in the
relating of the parts of pure experience. Nevertheless he maintains a certain openess in his attitude
to metaphysical problems and does not dismiss them as so much nonsense [h]. Instead he says that various claims or
beliefs (for example, about the existence of God, 'things in themselves', or consciousness) are
simply not provable (or indeed disprovable) by purely intellectual processes
[see Varieties of Religious Experience]. The 'generalized conclusion' of what he calls
his 'radical empiricism' is that the knowable universe has in
itself a continuous unified structure which is independent of our categories [i]. As for knowledge itself, he says (quoting Grote) each act of cognition implies
the existence of a 'feeling' (that is, Lockean 'idea') which we can be said to
have acquaintance with. This knowledge is 'phenomenal'. But we also have
knowledge about these ideas which is
more conceptual or intellectual and expressed in judgements or propositions. All qualities of feeling, so long as there is
anything outside of them which they resemble, are feelings of qualities of existence, and perceptions of outward fact they
point to the reality. Solipsism is avoided because we
believe our percepts are possessed by us in common; and this is tested out in
practice [j]. James thus supports his philosophical
position by his pragmatic method
though he grants that it could also be held by non-pragmatists. He also allows that one can reject his radical empiricism and still be a pragmatist
[Preface].
Although a 'radical empiricist' James is
not committed to determinism. He affirms the
(trans-categorial) reality of causal connections but at the same time he wants
to find a place for human free will. This is accommodated within the general context of his account of chance
and continuity in the universe [k]. Chance is illustrated by novelty which emerges from processes of
continuous change although not logically or ontologically already implicit in
them. But it may be not fully understood
in terms of scientific laws and may be
ultimately inexplicable.
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND/ PSYCHOLOGY
[2] [See Principles
of Psychology.] James was a psychologist as well as a
philosopher. What he says about the
'mind' is therefore of considerable interest. Starting from the fact that man is a living functional unity and rejecting all a priori metaphysics, James develops a generally descriptive
approach, that is, he selects, classifies, and analyses assumptions in
the light of our own interests (for example, as scientists, philosophers), and
articulates the consequences of such classification. He appeals to introspection, but he says this reveals no special infallible
status for mental contents; they can be assessed only in relation to
what he calls the 'final consensus' of our later knowledge. According to James, what is revealed to introspective observation is thoughts, feelings, and sensations [a]. He draws attention to thought in
particular, which he says is characterized by five features. Thought belongs to an active
personal consciousness or 'self'; it is constantly changing; it is a continuous
stream; it deals with objects independent from itself; it is selective and has
'interests'. He rejects views which
analyse thought as passive, the 'object' of perception and unambiguously
categorizable. Thought is a function of a purposive and ordering
mental life. And, indeed, in the context of his purposive
instrumentalism in general he seems to argue that there is no clear dividing
line between the mental and the physical [b]. He calls this view 'neutral monism'.
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION
[3] [Pragmatism,
Lecture VIII; also The Varieties of
Religious Experience.] Given James's commitment to 'experience', how can he
account for belief in God? Consistent with his method his answer is
pragmatic. It might seem that religious
belief goes beyond experience; and James certainly rejects the possibility that God's existence (or
non-existence) can be proved intellectually. But he appeals instead to "inner personal experiences" which put him in
touch with a "wider self", "a superhuman life", "higher part of the universe"
with which we are "co-conscious", and which has an effect in the world [a]. At the same time, such a being must be finite in view of the
presence of moral and natural evil [b]. Our aim must therefore be to cooperate with God to make things better,
though the outcome is not certain. James
therefore calls his approach 'meliorism' rather than 'optimism'. If we believe, then at least we must test our ethical and religious beliefs
in action [c]. This is his doctrine
of "the will to believe". But he advocates no commitment to any
particular religious orthodoxy.
CRITICAL SUMMARY
James is notable for his
emphasis on openness to all kinds of experience, for the monist features of his
philosophy, and for his pragmatic account of truth. With reference to the latter, however, he
does seem to oscillate between a view that 'true' is defined in (practical) terms of 'verifiability' (or successful 'working')
and the view that truths are in some sense 'made' by the verification of a
belief (verification thus being a test or sign). The latter approach fits in better with his
'anti-realist' and nominalist tendencies. The former view also raises the problem of truths as yet unverified
how can we know? Nevertheless, it can be
said that James's blending of an implicitly realist correspondence theory with
a coherence theory of truth (expressed in terms of consistency and
'satisfaction' despite the ambiguity of this term) has much to commend
it. On the debit side, his employment of
a wide notion of experience might suggest that anything is admissible to
support verification. What does constitute an adequate test? This problem becomes particularly acute in
his treatment of religion and God.
His general monism that everything is
made of a 'primal stuff', namely pure experience has the merit of avoiding
difficulties associated with both rationalist dualism and narrow
empiricism. But it can be questioned
whether, by referring to different 'functions' within the totality of 'pure'
experience, he has accounted satisfactorily for the distinction between the
knower and the known, the subject and the object. His distinction between 'pure' and
categorizing 'ordinary' experience, which leads to formal monism, is, however, a potentially fruitful one, although it
needs more working out than he provided.
James: [of many works] The
Varieties of Religious Experience: A
Study in Human Nature (1902); Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking (1907); The Meaning of Truth (1909); A Pluralistic Universe (1909); Essays in Radical Empiricism (1912). There are numerous editions of
some of these texts. There is a useful
single volume edition of Pragmatism and The Meaning of Truth, with and introduction by A. J. Ayer
Studies
G. Bird, William
James (The Arguments of the Philosophers).
G.E.
Moore, Philosophical Studies, "William James' 'Pragmatism' ".
R. B. Perry, In the Spirit of William James.
B.
Russell, Philosophical Essays,
"William James' 'Conception of Truth' and 'Pragmatism' ".
T. L. S. Sprigge, James and Bradley: American Truth and British
Reality.
Collection
of essays
R. A.
Putnam (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to William James.
CONNECTIONS
James