BRADLEY
(1846 1924)
ABSOLUTE
IDEALISM
Francis Bradley, a
vicar's son, was born in Clapham, Surrey. The eminent literary critic A.C. Bradley was his brother. He was educated at Cheltenham College, Marlborough
College (where a half-brother was headmaster), and at University College,
Oxford. In 1869 he gained his degree in
classics and philosophy, and in 1870 he was elected to a non-teaching
Fellowship at Merton College. He
thereafter devoted himself to writing. He was appointed to the Order of Merit in 1924.
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND LOGIC
[1] [Principles of Logic.] Bradley makes a clear separation between logic and psychology [a]. He also rejects the empiricist approach which holds that logic starts
with terms (subjects and predicates) and the ideas they are supposed to denote
which are then 'associated' in the mind. For Bradley we must
begin with judgements as single entities. The view that judgements link together
diverse ideas is untenable because what may seem to be a single idea will prove to be complex. (Proper names too must be understood as
connoting attributes and are thus akin to descriptions.) Neither can it accommodate such judgements as
'A and B are equal', or 'There is an X' on account of the difficulty in
identifying a subject. Indeed, relations cannot be accommodated
within the traditional subject-predicate framework. In acts of judgement we refer ideas or concepts constituting propositions to a Reality, a universal
meaning' beyond the act [b].
The 'contents' of the mind are thus not to regarded as purely mental or
psychical but, by virtue of their reference, as symbolic and possessing
meaning. He goes on to argue that all judgements are general. This is clear in universal judgements, for
example, 'All cats are mammals'. Here we
are saying that if something is a cat, then it also possesses the property of
being a mammal. It is thus hypothetical
and could be true even if there were no cats in existence. This is the case also of singular judgements,
for example, 'I have a toothache'. The
references of 'I' and 'toothache' will
differ with the individuals making the judgement. There must therefore be general ideas and
always some generality in such judgements. And this is not avoided by the use of proper names ('Jones' has
attributes which exist over a period of time) or terms such as 'here' and 'now'
(which also must be general if they are to have significance). More radically Bradley argues that all judgements are ultimately
about Reality as a whole; there are no isolated particular facts [c]. Suppose I say 'There is a cat'. When I do this I am abstracting a part of
what I actually say. To avoid this
'distortion' of reality I should have to situate the cat in the environment, in
the context of which it is a cat. The
real but hidden subject of the judgement is Reality as a whole to which all
judgements are related. It is in the
light of this view that Bradley argues
that relations should be
'internalized': a fact can be understood
only in terms of its relation to others; single facts cannot exist in isolation [d]. In the case of negative judgements, for
example, 'X is not Y', he says we are then affirming a property or properties
of X which stops it becoming a Y. Affirmative judgements are thus primary. As for universal judgements, although more general they involve even
greater abstraction and are thus further from Reality. Thus there is, for
Bradley, a 'gap' between
thought and the ultimate Reality. However, long after his major metaphysical work had been published, he seemed to be committed to a
view of logic as itself part of and as a means of penetrating the Real [See Principles of Logic, 2nd
edition] [e].
[2] Bradley says that
there are other kinds of inference than the Syllogism, for example, inferences
based on relations, which cannot be forced into this
mould. After suggesting and then criticizing the view that making an inference
consists in the discovering of a relation and the construction of a synthesis
uniting terms, he proposes a wider view which reflects the account already
given of judgements as abstracting from Reality. Inference involves reasoning; and to reason is not just to link two terms by means of another but to engage
in a constructive 'ideal experiment' on a datum. To say A is B and B is C is to link A-B-C as an 'ideal whole', which can then
be understood as a discovery of connections between predicates of Reality. The necessity of the inference is defined in
terms of 'the ideal self-development of an object' which, however, for us finite
beings is never complete [a]. Inference for Bradley thus also involves an 'ideal content' and hence
generality. The particular facts from which we start must
already be in some sense ordered and defined in terms of a theory and therefore
a 'universal'. He therefore denies that
traditional inductive procedures, whether from particulars to particulars or
from particulars to universal judgements, can provide us with knowledge. However, he rejects the utilization of a 'dialectic' grounded in
formalistic 'categories' [b].
METAPHYSICS/ MIND/ PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION
[3] [Appearance and Reality.] Bradley starts from the assumption that,
despite his reservations concerning the limitations of thought, it is possible
to discover a general
metaphysical view of Truth and Reality which satisfies the intellect. This view is grounded in the notion
that Reality is One,
a presupposition which is in a sense a matter of faith. However, Reality and Thought (the Rational) are distinct notions (constituting,
respectively, 'existence' and 'essence'). In a later essay he says the One is 'given' to us as
"feeling-experience" of a "many felt in one" [Essays on Truth and Reality, ch. VI]. This "immediate feeling" is the starting point for our "knowing
and being in one" [a]; and from it in
due course relations emerge. It is the
job of metaphysics to try to articulate, understand, and if possible prove
these assumptions. He proceeds [ A & R, Book I, ch. i] by attempting
to show that many of the
concepts of common sense or philosophy, in terms of which we usually understand
the world, lead to contradictions or even unintelligibility. He argues firstly that if secondary qualities are
appearances then primary qualities cannot stand by themselves. Materialism as a theory of reality is
therefore untenable. Analysis of
the reality of things in terms of qualities (substances and attributes) is
likewise incoherent [ii]. We say a lump
of sugar is white, hard, and sweet. Its
reality cannot be just a plurality of qualities. But if we think of it as the unity of these
properties in a relation, we will be led to say that A's being related to B
means either that A is A or A is other than A. Similarly [iii] there are difficulties with qualities and relations
themselves. It is equally problematic to
talk of qualities without relations or to talk of them as having them. Qualities can be shown both to make their
relations and to be made by them; while relations can be shown to be nothing or
to give rise to an infinite regress. In
subsequent chapters Bradley deals with space and time [iv], motion and change
[v], and causation [vi]. We can show, he
says, that space and time
must be both more than relations and yet a set of relations. As for causation, we can prove it to be both continuous and not
continuous. He then argues [vii]
that the concept of activity is riddled with inconsistencies. There is thus nothing left to the notion of
things as such. All talk of primary or secondary qualities,
relations, space and time, causation, etc. must therefore belong to the world
of appearance [b].
[4] Having dealt with
the external world Bradley discusses the 'inner' self [ix, x]. Is this not real? He rejects supposed 'intuitions' of the self or of a pure active
transcendental Ego, and also any analysis of someone's self in terms of
discrete contents of experience because these are constantly
changing. Likewise neither bodily continuity nor
memory can be the criterion of personal identity; and it cannot be located in
any perception of activity or of mere feeling. The self thus seems to be definable only
negatively as a 'residue'. And if we argue that the reality of the self must
lie in some inner unity in which it inheres we are brought back again to the
problem of relations. That we have experience of the
self as a constant group of feelings
which are connected with pain and pleasure, Bradley says is not in doubt;
indeed it is the highest form of experience. But, like the external world, it too must be regarded as appearance and
therefore erroneous. Immediate
experience is non-relational [a]. In the final chapters of Book I [xi, xii] Bradley concludes that the doctrine of phenomenalism,
while useful, gives us only the presentations of the moment or leads to
preposterous inconsistencies. The
alternative (dualist) theory of things in themselves is rejected as absurd [b]. How could they be related? Whether we start from the 'appearances' or from the 'reality' we are led
into difficulties.
[5] In Book II [especially xiii-xv] Bradley
presents his positive thesis about the Oneness of Reality. However, he stresses that, in so far as what appears
exists, has being, it is not to be set apart from the Real. On the contrary it has to be understood as
the appearance of the Real [a]. Considered as experienced, as
the object of discursive thought, the world of appearance is riddled with
contradictions. Nevertheless, when it is
regarded as taken up into the totality (the Absolute) all contradictions are
removed; or, looked at from the higher standpoint, the Absolute itself
must be one system, "a single and all-inclusive sentient experience, which
embraces every partial diversity in discord" [xiv]. In the Absolute a 'fusion' is achieved between Thought and Reality [xv] which for Bradley
are distinct notions, the Real being the 'existence' of a thing (that it is),
the Thought its 'essence' or qualities of a thing (what it is). He is critical of the view that that Reality is Thought or the Rational, and that only the Rational is Real, to be revealed to the intellect through
abstract categories and the 'dialectic'. Rather it is through judgement, as he understands it, and working on
appearance, that a move can be made towards reconciling the 'that' and the
'what' in the 'ideal synthesis' [xv]. As he says [Logic]:
That the glory of this world in the end is
appearance leaves the world more glorious, if we feel it is a show of some
fuller splendour; but the sensuous curtain is a deception and a cheat, if it
hides some colourless movement of atoms, some spectral woof of impalpable
abstractions, or unearthly ballet of bloodless categories.
Bradley thus seems to mean that the Absolute is that supra-relational totality in which
all finitude and distinction has been eliminated. "Feeling", he says, "supplies us with a
positive idea of non-relational unity" [xxvii]. But the idea is imperfect in that feeling is only an aspect of sentience
which in the Absolute additionally
includes but transcends sensation, thought, desire, and will. He also thinks of the Absolute as spiritual [xxvii]. However, this is not to attribute any kind of
personality to it. It is spiritual only in the sense that it is a
unity or manifold in which externality has ceased [b]. This raises questions concerning Bradley's view on (1) individual,
finite selves [xxiii, xxvi], and (2) God and religion [xxv].
Consistently with his assumptions and arguments he says that finite bodies and souls, while
imperfect appearances and therefore 'untrue', possess a degree of reality in so
far as they are appearances of the Absolute [c]. From this standpoint souls are less unreal than physical bodies; they
show a greater degree of self-dependence. As appearances,
both body and soul are "inconsistent abstractions". Bradley is therefore doubtful that we can
admit any kind of personal immortality [d]; the
transformation that body and soul undergo in the Absolute would seem to rule
this out. Likewise, if the Absolute is non-personal
it cannot be God [e] not least because
the Absolute is appearances (albeit transformed). It follows that religion comprehends
metaphysics yet is wider [xxvl].
[6] Underlying Bradley's discussion is a commitment to the view that
there are degrees of truth and reality [xxiv]. The further an appearance is from self-consistency and
relational inclusiveness the less real and the less true it is said to be, the criteria being coherence and comprehensiveness, though at
the same time he holds the view that propositions are true as such by virtue of
their correspondence to
reality [a]. Perfect truth, however, is an ideal to which
no finite thinking being can attain, not least because if we could develop a
scheme for grasping the totality we should lose sight of the particular
concrete facts. Nevertheless, Bradley
says we can appeal to "the
satisfaction of a want of our nature" as a criterion of truth [b]. In other words, the greater our satisfaction
the higher the degree of truth we may suppose ourselves to have
distinguished. The smaller the degree of
truth there is in appearance the correspondingly greater is the degree of
'untruth' in the error.
ETHICS
[7] Although Bradley's Ethical Studies antedated Appearance
and Reality, his metaphysics of the
Absolute is implicit in it. (Ethics are also discussed in the latter work
[xxv].) He starts [Essay I] by
considering the concept of responsibility in relation to two views of human
action. If we are to be held responsible
for our actions, we must accept personal identity: the actions must be ours; we must be
intelligent to know the circumstances; and we must be moral agents. Theories both of determinism and
indeterminism are inconsistent with these requirements [a]. What then is the end of morality'? Bradley says it is self-realization [b], "as
the self-conscious member of an infinite whole, by realizing that whole in
yourself " [II]. Before developing this
thesis he criticizes the
ethical theories of hedonism [III] and duty for duty's sake [IV]. Hedonism, the view
that man's good is pleasure, conflicts with its own psychology, and the end is
illusory. Further, to attempt to
introduce qualitative distinctions into the concept of pleasure is to appeal to a different account of the
good. Bradley sees utilitarianism as thereby tacitly introducing self-realization as the
proper end of human action which is inconsistent with hedonism. As for duty-for-duty's sake, he argues that
this notion is grounded in an empty abstraction; the theory is
self-contradictory; and the categorical imperative is impracticable [c]: it enjoins action for the sake of a form, an
unreal self .
What is it then to realize oneself as the
self-conscious member of an infinite whole? [V] Bradley's central claim is
that it is only in the
context of the social organism that
the individual can identify himself with the good will (which entails
his refusing to identify himself with the bad will of his private self); for
the good will is the universal will. To be moral I must will my
"station and its duties". By this
Bradley means not that there is a certain position or status in a social hierarchy
to which one is inflexibly bound, perhaps by accident of birth, for example,
but rather that one has certain functions, reflecting intelligence and learned
skills, and that it is these which determine one's duties in the family or
wider society of state or nation. At the same time, the individual
has a moral duty to realize himself [d] qua artist, scientist, and so on, quite
apart from any consideration of the benefit that his activities might in
general have for society at large. It
follows of course that morality
for Bradley is relative (to
different societies and cultures) [e]. And indeed it must be; for there can be no universal "full-fledged"
moral ideas which have fallen down from heaven, as he puts it, if the
individual is to achieve self-realization. But morality is nonetheless real and indeed is projected towards ever
higher realization [VI]. In fact Bradley says it is an endless process and can never be realized in the
objective world of the state but only for religious consciousness in the
"infinite whole" [f].
In the final Essay [VII] (which
anticipates his discussion in ch. xxv of Appearance and Reality) Bradley tries to show that self-realization involves both
selfishness and 'self-sacrifice'. Selfishness here is, however, 'proper egoism' and acceptable. It is not, for example, pleasure-seeking; nor
does it involve actions which are done at the expense of other people. Rather it may be understood as self-assertion
and characterized by single-mindedness the determination to realize or
perfect oneself using all the materials at one's disposal. But I may choose to achieve my moral end by
attending to the needs of other people (altruism). On the other hand my individuality may suffer
through lack of attention to, say, my health. This is self-sacrifice. Nevertheless it is at the same time a form of self-realization, in that
it involves renouncing a particular mode of existence in favour of something
higher. However, both approaches come together, Bradley says, and
are transcended in the Absolute [g]. It is in popular ethics that they are separated and the good identified
(unsuccessfully) with one or the other. As for evil, it is
obviously real for us, and indeed Bradley considers it as a precondition for
morality; without pain and suffering the notion of our real and 'whole'
self overcoming our 'bad self' (which is
only a formal collection of bad habits and desires not a genuine unity), with
a view to achieving harmony, would have
no purchase. From the standpoint of the Absolute there is
neither evil nor morality [h].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Bradley was the
greatest of the British Idealists. His
system of absolute idealism has the merit of avoiding, in its content,
language, and application, the worst excesses of his German idealist
antecedents. He is significant also for
his criticism of the empiricists for subordinating logic to psychology. His ethics, with its central concept of one's
'station and duties', has often been underrated and deserves wider attention as
offering an alternative to Kant's formalism and Mill's hedonistic
utilitarianism. In general it can be
said that Bradley's achievement is impressive for his detailed argumentation
over a range of concepts in his search for truth. There are of course difficulties with his
system.
(1) While they accepted his
attack on psychologism, Moore and Russell rejected his doctrine of internal
relations; and most philosophers today would agree with this criticism.
(2) It has been claimed that there is some
inconsistency between the implications for self, space and time, and so on of
his account of predication as identity (Appearance
and Reality, Book 1) which he
had rejected in his Logic and his
account of degrees of reality in Book II. His concept of the Absolute itself is not clearly defined, being
described only in terms of transformed appearances. However, this would seem to be a necessary
consequence of his premisses: categorization distorts the Real; the Real cannot be known except
through appearance. In extrapolation to
the Absolute all distinctions have to be dissolved.
(3) In his ethics there is a problem relating to
individual liberty. Is this concept
consistent with his view that the self is but appearance? Does the self when 'realizing' itself for
religious consciousness in the infinite whole retain its selfhood? Many critics have also argued that
individuality is even compromised at the level of appearance, to the extent
that Bradley stresses the primacy of the social organism. Furthermore, while self-realization may be
regarded as a desirable ideal, what is the justification for the claim that it
is our moral duty to realize
ourselves through our work or vocation?
Bradley: Ethical Studies (1876); Principles
of Logic (1883; 2nd edition 1922); Appearance and Reality (1893); Essays on Truth and Reality (1914). A useful collection is Writings
on Logic and Metaphysics edited and with introductions by J. W. Allard and
G. Stock.
Studies:
Introductory
R.
Wollheim, F. H. Bradley.
Advanced
T. S. Eliot, Knowledge
and Experience in the Philosophy of F. H. Bradley.
T.
Sprigge, James and Bradley: American Truth and British Reality.
Collection of essays
A. R. Manser and G.
Stock (eds), The Philosophy of F. H. Bradley.
CONNECTIONS
Bradley