SCHELLING
(1775 1854)
AESTHETIC
IDEALISM
Friedrich
Schelling, a Lutheran pastor's son, was born at Leonberg, near Stuttgart. He was educated at the Bebenhausen Cloister
School and at the Universities of Tübingen (theology and philosophy) and
Leipzig (science and medicine). At Tübingen he was a friend of Hegel and
Hölderlin. His first book (1795) was
admired by Fichte whose colleague he became when appointed to a professorship
at Jena in 1798. While there he was in
close contact with leading figures of Romanticism and was also co-editor with
Hegel of the Critical Journal of
Philosophy. He later lectured at
Würzburg, Stuttgart and Erlangen before being appointed to the chair at Munich
in 1827. He died in Switzerland.
METAPHYSICS/ KNOWLEDGE
Schelling's writings
seem to show that his thought was continuously developing, with a view to achieving what he called his 'System of Absolute Identity' [Exposition of my System of Philosophy,
1801]. This work can be seen as an
attempt to show that his Philosophy of
Nature (in a number of early books, 1797-9) and his system of Transcendental Idealism complement each other and underlie his final
views concerning the relationship of the finite world and the infinite
Absolute.
[1. Philosophy of Nature see especially On the True Concept of Nature Philosophy.]
[1] Although he started out from a Fichtean
position which emphasized the primacy of an unlimited Ego, Schelling came to
regard the 'objective'
world of Nature (matter) and the 'subjective' Ego (spirit Geist) as equally real and originally a
unity and not distinct in Kant's sense. As he says [Ideas towards a
Philosophy of Nature] "Nature becomes invisible spirit; spirit becomes
invisible Nature". Nature and Spirit may be
regarded as developing in parallel [a]. In his early work is he is concerned principally with showing how man's conscious mind
emerges from Nature seen as controlled by an unconscious, creative, intelligent
active principle (Ttigskeitprinzip)
or 'world-soul' [b].
The self-limitation of consciousness through reflection introduces finitude
into itself and brings about a differentiation from Nature. This split has to be restored on a higher
level of philosophical reflection. If mechanism and teleology are
to be reconciled, we need to see Nature as a unified, dynamic, developing,
self-organizing and teleological system which admits of different levels [c] it can be seen as an early stage of
Spirit. Schelling says that Nature is
intrinsically intelligible as recognised in its self-reflection (revealed
through human thought). To justify this view he undertakes a 'metaphysical deduction'. He firstly distinguishes between Nature as natura naturans and as natura
naturata. As the former it
is 'subjective', primary, productive Nature, the 'universal pattern'. The latter is the 'objective' system of
finite and temporal particular things constituting Nature's phenomenal being
the symbol, as it were, of natura
naturans. Schelling thinks of Nature
in both these aspects as manifestations of the Absolute in, respectively, the
('inner') ideal and the ('outer') real orders. For each of these he traces three 'moments' in the
Absolute considered as (a) a timeless and eternal act of self-knowledge, and
(b) as the intuited Ground of the ideal and real. With respect to the former the Absolute is
understood as 'objectifying' itself in Nature, transforming itself into
subjectivity, and then achieving a synthesis of both. Considered from the second standpoint, again the Absolute passes
through three phases. Nature as
real objectification of the Absolute is brought into the ideal realm of 'representations' (in the human knowing
mind); and the two realms are then seen to be interdependent and
inseparable. The Absolute for Schelling at this stage is thus a
pure identity of subjectivity and objectivity [d].
Now, if he is to realize the unity of
Nature he needs also a 'theoretical
deduction' of bodies and forces force,
or 'pure activity', being the common ground of Nature and the Ego, and the manifestation
of a process of infinite never ending self-activity. This is a
speculative not an empirical physics; and it exhibits the teleological pattern
in natura naturata. He distinguishes a 'lower' inorganic or mechanistic and a 'higher' organic level. But he rejects any attempt to 'reduce' the
latter to the former. There is no
opposition between them, both being continuous aspects of Nature as a whole. However, Schelling supposes that for the
objective phenomenal world to emerge the infinite productive activity,
organizing principle, or 'world-soul' (as act of the Absolute) has to be
constrained [gehemmt]. He identifies three stages or 'potencies'
(Potenzen] of Nature [e]. The first potency arises when Nature (as exhibited in repulsive
forces) is controlled by a limiting (attractive) force material bodies
possessing mass then arising through the synthesis of the two forces. Through a
further process of limitation the various magnetic, electrical, and chemical processes
of phenomenal nature are manifested as a result of the second potency. This 'universal mechanism' also assimilates
at the higher level the forces and synthesis of the first potency. The third potency occurs at the level of the organism and comes
about as a result of the synthesis of the first two potencies, whereby all the
forces acting through matter are exhibited in the activities of sensibility,
irritability (that is, responsiveness to stimuli), and reproduction in various
degrees of individual organisms man being the highest and the point of
transition between subjective representations and objective Nature.
[2. Transcendental Idealism see System of Transcendental Idealism.]
[2] [Transc. Idealism,
Part I.] In
Schelling's Philosophy of Nature we move from the Objective to the
Subjective. His Transcendental Idealism involves an attempt to move from the
Subjective to the Objective. But he
regards the two approaches as complementary in that to account for knowledge as
the uniting of subject and object we must first think of the two poles as
separate. He says it is the Ego, that is, "the act of self-consciousness in general", that
constitutes knowledge of the identity of subject and object. This is
because as an
'intellectual intuition' it produces itself as the object of transcendental
thought from within itself as subject [a]. Starting from the certainty of the 'I think' (cogito) Schelling is therefore concerned primarily to trace the
development of consciousness from unconscious Nature as the practical
act of the Absolute Ego; and he has in effect to show that the external
objective world is a necessary presupposition. Self-awareness
requires awareness of other egos. In Part I he starts by distinguishing three 'epochs'. Firstly, consciousness emerges from sensation and perception and rises
to the level of 'productive (creative) intuition'. (This process
corresponds to the construction of matter in his Philosophy of Nature [see sec. 1].) The second epoch is the transition from productive intuition to the level of reflection. The Ego as unlimited act unconsciously
limits itself by positing a non-Ego, characterized by sensible objects,
distinct from the Ego, and structured by the imposed categories of space, time,
and causality. Lastly, the infinite Ego returns to itself through its self-determining will
abstracting itself from the non-Ego. This gives rise to individual human self-consciousness and intelligence
as a free and active power [b]. Man's actions are understood as being both free and necessary. Their freedom lies in their inner necessity
in that actions stem from his self-positing ego [c]. Man acts in a particular way because it is in
his intelligible character to do so. [For his later account of freedom see sec. 6.]
[3. Identity Philosophy see especially Presentation
of My System of Philosophy.]
[3] In his earlier
writings Schelling had argued for the identity of Nature and Spirit the unity
being attributable to the Absolute as the explanation and ground. In later works [for example, Presentation and Lectures on the Method of Academic
Study] he placed more emphasis on the Absolute as the
ultimate object of philosophical investigation and conceived it as the total indifference of
subjective and objective. At
times he also thinks of the Absolute as the supreme 'Divine' Idea which
contains within itself ideas of all finite things [Bruno: a Discourse]. And he
interprets the unity in various ways. It is not only the identity of
opposites (the subjective and the objective), but is also the identity of the
multiplicity of opposites and the unity itself (an 'identity of the identity'); or it is the identity which obtains
between the finite and the infinite [see sec. 6.] Individual things are regarded by Schelling as possessing both real and
ideal elements [a]. In phenomenal things the real is predominant,
while in spiritual phenomena the real elements are subordinate to the ideal. We have only limited knowledge
of individual things (as illusory particulars) through the imagination ('inadequate
ideas'). They can, however, be grasped
as ideal realities when considered as existing in the Absolute and viewed sub specie aeternitatis. However, they then lose their individualities
and differences. Moreover, the Cartesian cogito is now understood as giving us no
transparency; individual consciousness and thinking belongs to the Absolute
Identity (or God) [b]. But we do not have
access to the Absolute itself; our knowledge is confined to the relation between finite things and the
Absolute. Although the Absolute is the
ultimate object of philosophical speculation, we can know it only as it appears to our empirical consciousness
in the two series: the real objective 'potencies' of the
Philosophy of Nature and the ideal
subjective 'epochs' of his Transcendental Idealism. We can, however, 'intuit' the Absolute by thinking away all finite
attributes or distinctions (the negative approach) [c].
ETHICS/ POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
[4] [Transc.
Idealism, Pt II.] The will as 'self-idealizing
activity' (which is to be distinguished from 'natural impulse') attempts to
actualize in the objective world the ideal which belongs to the ego as
subjective, thereby enabling the ego to realize itself as intelligence. In the first stage will appears as 'drive' (Trieb). In the second stage this splits into 'natural drive' and moral law the Categorical Imperative: you ought to will only that
which other intelligences can will; and this must be pure self-determination. For this to be achieved action in the world
is required; and thereby conscious Spirit becomes objectified [a]. Finally, free will appears which facilitates choice between drive and
moral law. This in turn leads to
Schelling's deduction of a
rational State and a system of rights which
can provide the framework for the rule of law necessary for the achievement of
individual freedom and self-realization, and for moral action [b]. To avoid conflicts between states he proposes
a federation which must both recognise basic principles and agree to submit to
fundamental law. Endless progress towards the ideal of the perfect
political society which exhibits universal moral order is implicit in human
history. He thus regards this as a
continual revelation of the Absolute [c]. While actions in the historical process are freely chosen,
Schelling argues that at
the same time there is a necessity in the process, which leads to an absolute
synthesis or reconciliation of human actions [d] even when they are seemingly willed for selfish ends, in which case the
necessity lies at the level of the unconscious.
AESTHETICS
[5] [gen 5] Philosophy of Art [Transcendental Idealism, Part III and Philosophy of Art] is
significant for Schelling not only as a field of study which is of interest in
itself but also because he regards works of art as finite revelations of the
infinite Absolute. Art, he says, is grounded in the
power of productive intuition directed towards a concrete manifestation [a] in the work of a creative genius. When the artist creates
he is both conscious that he is producing, say, a painting, but yet his
creative power originates from within his unconscious. The observer in turn
contemplates the work of art and feels an 'infinite satisfaction' which is an indication of the identity of
the objective real and the subjective ideal, and of the unconscious and the conscious. Although it is not actually known, this actual reality lying behind
the sphere of knowledge as constituted by the one absolute 'act of
self-consciousness' is revealed to the
individual ego through aesthetic intuition [b].
(This is to be contrasted with Will, and with Hegelian 'Logic' and Reason as
supposed sources of insight into the Real.)
As for his aesthetics as such, Schelling
says particular things are
beautiful in so far as they are in and accord with eternal ideas which enter in
and are intuited in them. Beauty is thus
identical to truth, which is the conformity
of the particular to the universal idea [c]. Mediation between the universal and particular, and the production of
concrete images, is effected through a symbolic world of 'poetic
existence', the source of which is mythology [d]. Schelling's aesthetics is thus teleological,
the purpose of art being to realize the finite through beauty thereby
reconciling history and Nature, and the theoretical with the practical [e]. Moreover, in all the productive intelligent activity (unconscious but
manifested in organisms) is conscious in the creating, though unconscious in
the created work.
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION
[6] [See
especially Philosophy and Religion and Inquiries into the Nature of Human
Freedom.] Schelling started out from a broadly Platonic view,
arguing that the Divine is
reflected in the Eternal Idea, which in turn is manifested in the eternal ideas
of Nature the object of human consciousness through which God knows
Himself. He then seems to have
oscillated between a pantheist and a transcendentalist account of God in
relation to the world. His position
might, however, be appropriately described as panentheistic: the world is grounded and exists in God infinite, pure identity, indifferent to the distinction between the
subjective and the objective. He
attributes personality to God as arising from Himself out of an impersonal
primitive 'original foundation' (Urgrund) or unconscious will to exist. God is conceived also as positing Himself
simultaneously as rational subjective will or love. (Indeed in his later work [Human Freedom] he seems to identify God as 'primal being' with pure
Willing eternal, independent, self-affirming) [a]. (These positings are non-temporal, not
successive. Schelling thinks of them as
different 'potencies' or moments in God's activity.) This accounts for His manifestation in the
world: constantly creating Himself God 'expands' Himself into
finitude, as a consequence of which the unity of the subjective and
objective is split. To explain the existence of
finite things the transition from natura
naturans to natura naturata Schelling introduces the idea of the Cosmic
Fall (Abfall): the world is a breaking away
from God through a 'leap'. This is
alienation from the Absolute. However, this creative process, like the positing of unconscious
will and rational will, is non-temporal and eternal [b],
and through it we as created beings see the world as finite and independent. God being identity of subject and object, His acts are both free and
necessary: indeed, they too are
identical. Similar considerations
apply to man. Freedom is an intrinsic characteristic of the
conscious will. But for freedom to be
activated it must operate in the context of an 'opposition'. This is what he calls the unconscious 'dark'
principle. And yet these opposing
principles must be in some sense identical [c]. While in God they are unified, in man they
are separate [see On the Nature of Human
Freedom]. What then of the existence
of evil, if God is the 'ground' of the finite world? Schelling's solution seems to be that what from man's point of view is
evil and real is from God's standpoint nothing. The potentiality for evil exists in the 'dark' ground even of God: but it is man alone that it is manifested in
consequence of his free will. However,
in the course of time through God's agency man's rational will will conquer his
lower impulses [d].
Religion, is important in Schelling's scheme of things in so far
as it affords a basis for
what he calls 'positive philosophy' [see especially Philosophy of Revelation and Philosophy
of Mythology], which he developed in his final period. It is a philosophy not based on conceptual thinking (ideas, logical
deduction, which constitute 'negative philosophy') but one which involves faith
in God as a personal being as a result of commitment by the will and thence
self-realization. Such a philosophy
works through history. And
Schelling argues that successively in myth, revealed (Christian) religion, and thereby in his philosophy of religion [e], God's inner 'potencies', the Fall, and
the return will be made manifest.
CRITICAL SUMMARY
While Fichte started out from Kant's second Critique, Schelling in general looked to
the Critique of Judgement. Critics differ as to how his philosophy
should be interpreted. (Interpretation
is not helped by the frequent changes in his views throughout his prolific
career.) A widely held position is that
he aimed to provide a comprehensive world-view, but no final system is achieved
in his writings. Rather his earlier
thought can be represented as an ongoing developing process, each phase,
however, perhaps emphasizing different aspects of his overall vision,
culminating in what he called his 'System of Absolute Identity'. This can be seen as an attempt to show that
his Philosophy of Nature and his system of Transcendental Idealism are
complementary and underlie his final but incomplete views concerning the
relationship of the finite world to the infinite Absolute as pure identity of
subjective and objective. Arguably Schelling
thus goes some way towards overcoming the dualism associated with both Kant and
Fichte, and in ways which have something in common with the approach developed
by Hegel. Indeed he seems to have felt
that Hegel had illegitimately appropriated his own ideas. In his last period (from the 1820s onwards)
he is severely critical of Hegel for passing beyond his (Schelling's) position,
and in particular, for attempting to deduce from
within Reason itself (that is, thought or the concept) its identification
with the Real (or Being). Rather, according
to Schelling, the identity of reality and rationality as the Absolute is a
presupposition of philosophical thought
and cannot be fully grasped by reason, which must start from that which is
external to itself, namely, the realm of contingent reality, that is, being or
nature.
His philosophy is of interest for a number
of reasons. (1) In his 'dialectic' of
knowledge he moves from sensation to perception, self-awareness in reflection,
to the will. (2) He emphasizes art (a)
as the means by which the activity of the organic self is rendered conscious,
and (b) as making possible the revelation of the infinite in the finite. (3) He points to man's self-realization
through myth and religion. Some
commentators have seen as implicit in this an anticipation of
existentialism. (4) In line with his
developing thought Schelling offers a number of different accounts of God as
will, a personal being, perfection, the original ground of being and yet also
non-being itself. However, this fourth
phase of his work was criticized by Hegel for what he saw as its irrationalism
and mysticism. We might also argue that
his treatment of the problems of human freedom, and of God and evil are open to
the charge of obscurity; and it is questionable whether he has resolved them
satisfactorily. More generally (and
especially from a Hegelian standpoint) it can be said that as Fichte's
philosophy is one-sided in its ethical basis so is Schelling's in the primacy
he accords to aesthetics. But, as
against Fichte, he does restore 'objectivity' to Nature. However, for many philosophers the most
serious objection is one that his system shares with all three German
Idealists: it postulates both that reality
is independent of mind and yet that each is determined by the other. Indeed, it would seem that the process of
self-knowing is the only 'reality'.
Schelling: [of many works not all of
which have been translated into English] Ideen zu einer Philosophie der
Natur als Einleitung in das Studium dieser Wissenschaft (1797) (Ideas
for a Philosophy of nature as Introduction to the Study of this Science,
trans. E. E. Harris
& P. Heath); System des
transcendentalen Idealismus (1800) (System
of Transcendental Philosophy,
trans. P. Heath); ber den wahren
Begriff der Naturphilosophie und die richtige Art, ihre Probleme zu lsen (1801)
(On the True Concept of Nature Philosophy
and the Right Way to Solve its Problems no English translation located); Darstellung meines System der Philosophie (1801) (A Presentation of my System of Philosophy no English translation located); Philosophie
der Kunst (1802-3) (Philosophy of Art, trans. and ed. D. W. Stott),
and ber das Verhältniss der bildenden Künste zu der Natur (1807)
(trans. as An Oration on the Relation Between the Plastic Arts and Nature by A. Johnson); Vorlesungen ber
die Methode des akademischen Studiums (1803) (Lectures on the Method of Academic Study, trans. as On University
Studies by E. S. Morgan); Philosophie
und Religion (1804) (Philosophy and Religion no English
translation located); Philosophische Untersuchungen ber das
Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit und die damit zusammenhngende Gegenstünde (1809) (Philosophical Investigations on the Essence of Human Freedom, trans. J. Gutman); Die Weltalter (1811) (The Ages of the World, trans. F. de W. Bolna, jr ); Philosophie der Mythologie (1842) (Philosophy of Mythology); and Philosophie der Offenbarung (1842-3) (Philosophy of Revelation) no translations available for the
last two but foreshadowed in Die Weltalter, and see Beach below. See also the collection of extracts from
Schelling in R. Bubnner (ed.), German Idealist Philosophy.
Studies
E. A. Beach, The Potencies of the
Gods: Schelling's Philosophy of
Mythology.
A. Bowie, Schelling and Modern European Philosophy.
W. Marx, The Philosophy of F. W.
J. Schelling: History, System, Freedom.
A. White, Schelling: Introduction to the System of Freedom.
Collection of essays
K. Ameriks (ed.), The Cambridge
Companion to German Idealism.
CONNNECTIONS
Schelling