DILTHEY
(1833 1911)
'CRITICAL
EMPIRICISM'/ HISTORICISM
Born at Biedrich near
Wiesbaden in Germany, the son of Lutheran theologian, Wilhelm Dilthey was educated at the Wiesbaden
Gymnasium and at the Universities of Heidelberg (theology) and Berlin (history
and philosophy), gaining his doctorate in 1864. After teaching for a time in secondary schools he became a university
professor successively at Basel, Kiel, Breslau, and finally Berlin in 1882. He lectured and wrote prolifically both on
philosophy and the history of ideas.
METAPHYSICS / 'PHILOSOPHY
OF LIFE'/ CULTURE
[1] Central to Dilthey's later philosophy [The Construction of the Historical World] is the concept of Life (Leben). By this he
means the totality of
human experience thoughts, feelings, actions, institutions, sciences,
religions, expressed through the multitude of different societies as a dynamic
historical process. Life is what
we actually experience: experience (Erlebnis) is 'lived',
arising as it does from the interaction of the whole individual (reason,
feeling, volition, as manifestations of the functional unity of his mental
life) with his social and cultural environment [a]. (This is to be contrasted with Nature itself, as studied by the natural
sciences [see sec. 2], which, he says, is produced independently of the active mind.) In Life we experience a relationship of unity
with other persons, and with phenomenal manifestations of culture works of art, religious ceremonies, and so
on, though these may be ultimately analysable into sensations and
impressions. The knowing subject is itself also part of Life
and cannot transcend it to know from some 'objective' or 'absolute'
standpoint. Ideas and values are all
produced by individuals situated and interconnected in particular societies or
cultures at particular times in history and are thus relative [b]. Life, he says, does not come to us as a mass
of disconnected elements. It is already connected, organized and
interpreted as a result of fundamental principles or categories. But these are
not a priori categories; they arise
out of empirical generalizations. Ultimately "the
mind understands only what it has created" [Construction of the Historical World]. The categories operate mainly at the
subconscious level, but we also use them intentionally and consciously so as to
make our experiences more meaningful. The basic categories, however,
cannot be fully explicated. Thus he identifies the cognitive concepts
of 'inner' and ' outer', which relate respectively to mental
contents and their expression in symbolic language, and through these we
attempt to understand the world of facts (the things and processes of independent Nature). Other categories are power, in terms of which we account for the
effects the environment, including other people, has on us (in the context of
scientific explanation this category would be termed causation); and value and purpose (which relate to feeling and
desire) [c], through
which we experience the present or look to the future, with a view to achieving
pleasure or happiness (wherein lies the good). He also identifies the
categories of 'development' and the 'ideal'. The primary
category, however, is that of meaning (Bedeutung). The central question he poses is, 'How is
meaningful experience possible?' Dilthey first understood meaning
as the means by which we experience, that is, 'relive' (nacherleben) the past. But later it became the category of which all
the others are different aspects, employed or manifested in different concepts [d]. The application of the categories (comprising thinking,
feeling, and desiring) gives rise to interpretations of Life myths, religions, works of art; while values and purposes
can be made explicit in moral principles and systems, political constitutions,
and so on. These various
interpretations together form different world-views (Weltanschauungen) each of which expresses Life albeit
partially and from particular standpoints [e]. Dilthey classifies these into three types: (1) naturalism; (2) the idealism of freedom;
(3) objective idealism.
While Dilthey seems to be committed to some form of relativism and
regards the 'world-views' as one-sided, he considers an intuitable overall
'vision' of reality as the ideal. However, he recognises that a complete or final synthesis cannot be
achieved [f].
METHODOLOGY/ KNOWLEDGE
[2] [See The Construction of the Historical
World.] A philosophy of life, if it
is to be as complete as possible, must rely not just on general observation of
events or on broad 'interpretations'. A
firm theory of knowledge and a reliable methodology will also be required. Dilthey distinguishes between the natural
sciences (Naturwissenschaften) and the 'cultural' or human sciences (Geisteswissenschaften)
(that is, the sciences of mental
life). The natural sciences are objective, systematic, and
involve observation, classification, induction and deduction, models and
hypotheses, testing procedures, and the formulation of general laws, and are
generally anti-metaphysical [a]. The human sciences may
use some or all of these elements, but in addition and essentially they are grounded in the lived
experiences and freely willed activities
of individuals and in the concept of understanding (Verstehen),
by which Dilthey means the grasping and penetration of some inner structure or
mental content idea, feeling, intention, which is expressed through empirical
phenomena such as gestures, words, or works of art. (In his early writings [especially Introduction to the Human
Sciences] Dilthey had interpreted this mental content psychologically and
indeed had regarded a scientific
or methodological 'descriptive' psychology as foundational for the human
sciences, but one which would examine causal relations and 'typologies' as well
as mental phenomena. However, later he thought of the 'inner life' more
transcendentally as spiritual, in terms of 'life relations' [b] which constitute
the conditions for the world to be understood as meaningful.) If understanding
is to be achieved, there are, he says, three conditions which have to be
met. (1) We have to be aware of the
mental processes which underlie our interpretations of human activities as
meaningful. This requires us also to
have some knowledge of psychology and literary studies of the individuals whose
lives and works we are seeking to understand. (2) We should study systematically the particular context (time, place,
situation) in which the expression (discourse, text, and so on) of the mental
contents occurs. (3) We should have a
comprehensive knowledge of the relevant social and cultural background. Dilthey adds that investigation of, for
example, works of art, texts, or political and legal constitutions may be more
complicated than the study of the thoughts and feelings of an individual; and
that such systems are therefore best dealt with as 'entities' which, although
part of the whole culture, have some independent existence.
HERMENEUTICS
[3] Life is of course not static, and change
takes place in a historical dimension. Dilthey's philosophy thus leads to a 'hermeneutic' a "critique of historical
understanding". Underlying his
project are three basic principles. (1) Everything that man says or does
is part of this continuing process and should be explained in
historical-cultural terms. This
means that our understanding of individuals, families, nations is not to be
measured against some abstract absolute standard; such 'entities' have
different expressions in different historical periods. (2) To achieve understanding we must enter imaginatively into
the points of view of individuals living in these periods. And this requires us first to be able to
experience and understand our own social-cultural context. We can then empathize with them and relive their experiences. (3) However, we must also recognise that the historian himself is limited
by his own prejudices and concerns, and that these presuppositions have to
enter into the 'meaning' or interpretation of the past [a].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Arguably the major figure in nineteenth century development of the
philosophy of culture and philosophical anthropology, Dilthey extended the
scope of hermeneutics beyond texts alone to take in all situations in which meaning
as subjective intention might be discovered by abstracting from and
transcending as far as possible from one's own individual and cultural
prejudices. The key features of his thought are his concepts of Life and
understanding, and the categories.
Subsequent debate has centred on the
question whether it is possible to discard prejudices and presuppositions to
achieve genuine insight into 'meanings'. To the extent that Dilthey's view of life as a historical-cultural unity
is one of a process of continual approximation to a putative objective vision of reality and human
self-knowledge, he may be supposed to have avoided the excesses of relativism
and historicism. Nevertheless some
later critics have argued that to acquire some grasp of meanings we should
actually have made use of the techniques and methods of interpretation
available in our own contemporary culture so as to achieve the fullest possible
(albeit necessarily incomplete) 'fusion' of our own 'horizons' (to use
Gadamer's phrase) with that of the object of our interpretation. In this respect Dilthey's hermeneutics has
been criticized as being limited or one-sided, and too optimistic as regards
the success of any interpretative venture.
Dilthey: [of many writings] Einleiting in die
Geisteswissenschaften (1883) (Introduction to the Human Sciences,
trans. R. J. Betzanos); Der Aufbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den
Geisteswissenschaften (1910 unfinished) (The Construction of the
Historical World in the Human Sciences). Selected passages from these works and manuscript notes are included in
H. A. Hodges, Wilhelm Dilthey: An
Introduction, and (more extensive)
in Rickman, H. P. (ed.), W. Dilthey: Selected Writings.
Studies
Hodges, H. A., The
Philosophy of Wilhelm Dilthey.
H.P. Rickman,
Wilhelm Dilthey: Pioneer of the Human Studies.
H. P. Rickman, Dilthey
Today: A Critical Appraisal of the
Contemporary Relevance of His Work.
T. Plantinga, Historical Understanding in the Thought of Wilhelm Dilthey.
CONNECTIONS
Dilthey