HEGEL
(1770 1831)
ABSOLUTE
IDEALISM
Georg
Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel was born in Stuttgart, the son of a civil servant. He was educated at the local Gymnasium and
then studied philosophy and theology at the University of Tübingen (where he
became friends with Schelling and the poet Hölderin). After graduating he
worked for seven years as a family tutor, during which time he started to write. In 1801 he
became a professor at Jena but had to leave when the university closed down in
1806 because of the Battle of Jena. He then
edited a newspaper, and was appointed Rector of a grammar school in Nuremburg. He was a professor at Heidelberg in 1816, and
two years later he succeeded Fichte in the chair at Berlin, where he died of
cholera.
[Sources: Hegel's philosophy is set out systematically
in his Encyclopedia of the Philosophical
Sciences, which is essentially a construction of the life of the
'Absolute'. In the earlier Phenomenology of the Spirit he had
sought to trace the development of consciousness through its various stages up
to the level of absolute or philosophical knowledge: but much of what he wrote in this book was
later incorporated into Part III of the Encyclopedia. Part I of the Encyclopedia, the
so-called 'Lesser Logic' was a revised version of his earlier Science of
Logic; Part II is his Philosophy
of Nature. The following account is
based largely on the Encyclopedia. References are to the 'Divisions' and chapters, and to the relevant
numbered sections (Part I: 1-244;
Part II: 192-298; Part III: 377-577].
Introductory Summary:
THE METAPHYSICAL SYSTEM/ KNOWLEDGE
[1] In common with his idealist
predecessors, Fichte and Schelling, Hegel built on the philosophy of Kant. But, as against the Königsberg philosopher,
he attributed to human reason the capacity to grasp the Real. There is for Hegel no unknowable 'thing-in-itself': Reality is knowable. The real is the rational, and the rational is
the real [a]. He also rejected the phenomenal
and noumenal dichotomy and the sharp division Kant made between reason and
sense/ feeling or desire; for Hegel the two aspects were reconciled in the Real [b]. Hegel's metaphysical system comprehends all aspects of his
philosophy theory of knowledge, philosophy of Nature, philosophy of mind,
ethics, aesthetics, philosophy of religion, and philosophy of history. The central concept is that of the Absolute,
the infinite creative totality in which all finite distinctions are
unified. He regards this as Spirit (Geist) and self-thinking thought, an
identity-in-difference of the ideal and real, of subjectivity and
objectivity. It is a necessary process
of self-development from potentiality to actuality, which reveals itself in and
through finite Nature, its self-knowledge being achieved through the
philosophical reflection of man (and
articulated finally, we might suppose, in Hegel's own thought and philosophy) [c].
METHODOLOGY
[2] The inner essence of the Absolute as it is 'in itself' is revealed
through logic. But this is neither the logic of Aristotle nor modern formal logic. Hegel's method is dialectical. Dialectic is to be understood as the
articulation, exploration, revelation of categories undergoing a progressive transformation culminating in the category of the
Absolute Idea [a]. Underlying this is a
distinction between understanding (Verstand) and reason (Vernunft). Through the understanding we may grasp concepts such as the finite and the infinite, the one and the
many, reality and appearance. Such polar oppositions may be important in our everyday practical lives
or in the sciences. But Hegel sees
reliance on the understanding as limited in so far as its concepts are
'static', rigid, and superficial; and it does not allow these 'contradictories'
to be overcome. The understanding cannot
supply us with knowledge of the life of the Absolute. To transcend oppositions, overcome contradictions, requires (dynamic) reason or speculative thought; this
alone can grasp how one concept or category can pass over into its opposite, both being united in a higher
identity-in-difference. Central to the
rational process is negation (for
Hegel to negate is to determine and to posit); and the process is triadic: a thesis is opposed by its antithesis; both
are taken up in a new synthesis. The
synthesis is in turn opposed by a new antithesis; and eventually the ultimate
self-explanatory principle is attained. This is the
dialectical method, motivated, as it were, by an inner necessity of Reason, an
Absolute process working through the finitude of the human spirit to resolve
'contradictions' and achieve self-knowledge. Put more simply, the Absolute comes to know itself through human
philosophical reflection [b]. Hegel's philosophical system is a 'deduction' (though not
in the narrow sense as used in formal logic) of the categories leading progressively through to ever
more coherent, that is, true intellectual revelations of the Real, culminating
in the category of the Absolute itself. These categories are at once
'definitions' of the Absolute and, as universal concepts, applicable to the
actual existent entities constituting the universe. And the Absolute is implicit in each individual category in
so far as each constitutes an element in the total system [c].
Hegel's metaphysical system, as
presented in the Encyclopedia:
[I. Logic]
[3] [Encl.I, 1-83] The function of logic (as Hegel
understands it) is to make possible the study of the Absolute or Idea as it is
'in itself ' as 'potential' rather than
'actual' Spirit, to reveal its inner essence through the dialectic
deduction of the categories by pure reason. The Absolute spirit as
self-thinking thought manifesting itself in finite Nature thereby comes to know
its own being. (Logic and metaphysics
thus coincide) [a].
[Division 1of the Logic] is the Doctrine of Being [84ff.]. The fundamental or first category, logically
and ontologically, is that of pure Being (Sein). But as it is completely empty or
indeterminate it passes over into non-Being or nothing. However, the 'contradiction' of Being and non-Being (thesis versus
antithesis) is resolved in the higher synthesis of Becoming [88]. Becoming is then
shown to give rise to Determinate Being [89] by removing from it the element of change and replacing it by
rest. Within the category of Determinate Being Quality as
thesis gives rise to Limit as antithesis, from which the synthesis of the 'True Infinite' is deduced [94] [b]. This in turn gives way to the category of
Being-for-self [96ff.] which
contains the triad The One, the Many, and Repulsion-Attraction. Hegel then moves from this to the spheres
firstly of Quantity [99] and then of Measure [107]. [To understand precisely how each category has been supposedly deduced
from that which precedes it the reader should read Hegel's own detailed account
in the Encyclopedia.]
.[Division 2] is the Doctrine of Essence (Wesen) [112-159]. Hegel calls the concepts in this Division
categories of reflection, in that they relate to a reflective consciousness
which has access to the inner essence lying behind Being in its phenomenal
existence. From the category of Essence
as Ground of Existence [115-128] he derives 'The Thing' an existent considered under the aspect of both
'reflection-into-self' (self-subsistence) and reflection-into-another
(dependence); while 'The Thing' is analysable into inherent dependent
properties, which in turn are seen as independent 'matters' of which a thing is
composed. This leads to a deduction
of Matter as such and its correlate, Form. Matter "the immediate unity of existence with itself", is "indifferent towards
specific character" and is thus is indeterminate, featureless; while Form, "the
reflective category of difference" constitutes and defines the thing's distinct
properties and their external relations to each other. As Hegel explains, the category of The Thing
as a totality is a contradiction:
On the side of its negative unity it is Form in
which Matter is determined and deposed to the rank of properties. At the same
time it consists of Matters, which in the reflection-of-the-thing-into-itself
are as much independent as they are at the same time negatived. Thus the thing
is the essential existence, in such a way as to be an existence that suspends
or absorbs itself in itself. In other words the thing is an Appearance or
Phenomenon. [128]
Actuality
(Wirklichkeit) [142-159] is the synthesis of (a) Essence
as Ground of Existence and (b) Appearance [131-140], that
is, the inner and outer aspects of Being. From Actuality he ultimately derives Substance and Existence, Cause
(active substance) and Effect (passive substance), and Reciprocity (in which
category activity is passivity and vice versa). Being and Essence in turn
produce a synthesis in the category of the Notion or Concept (Begriff)
[Division 3] [c]. Hegel's argument here is that while each category
in the category of Being is seemingly self-sufficient and immediate, and the
categories in the category of Essence are relational and mediational, the
category of the Notion is seen to be self-mediating, passing from itself into
its opposite yet remaining itself. This category of Notion [160] is subdivided into a formal or subjective aspect, which leads to a
deduction of logic in its traditional sense, and an objective aspect under
which are subsumed the categories of the concept of Nature (the 'sensuous'
realm) 'Mechanism' [195], 'Chemism' [200], and their synthesis as Teleology [204]. In the unity and
identity of the Subjective Notion and Objective Notion we have the the category
of the Idea [213]. This in turn has three phases: Life [216], Cognition [223], and the Absolute Idea [236]. This last is the synthesis of the life-process (in which the organic has
reabsorbed the inorganic into itself) and self-thinking thought or Spirit,
which both knows itself in and as the object: "The Absolute Idea
alone is being, eternal life, self-knowing truth, and it is all truth, it is the one subject-matter and content of philosophy" [Science
of Logic, 1781]. It is "the noesis noeseos which
Aristotle long ago termed the supreme form of the idea." [Encl. 236 n.] [d].
[II. Philosophy of Nature]
[4] [Encycl. II, 192-5] From
the Logical Idea Hegel moves to his Philosophy of Nature, which is the Absolute or Idea considered 'for itself ' as 'self-alienated' Spirit. As the means whereby the Absolute realizes
itself, comes to a knowledge of itself through the human spirit, Nature must be
a precondition for this process; and Hegel sees the deduction of Nature as
revealing it. The Absolute as Idea
cannot exist separate from Nature but is yet logically prior to it. Nature in its structure and universality is the manifestation of free
rational Spirit and is thus a necessary process, its explanation being given in terms of
reason; but considered in itself, in its concrete particularity, it is
abstracted from and is external to the Idea and is thus the realm of
contingency, though a contingency which is essential to Nature. Hegel says Nature is 'impotent' to keep
within the bounds of reason and thus far is irrational. Nature is a 'decline' (Abfall)
from the Idea. Thus we might say,
consistently with his dialectic, that Nature is both identity of necessity-in-contingency and
freedom-in-determinism. Contingent
Nature is a necessary realization of free Spirit and is knowable through the
dialectic. Clearly Hegel rejects the
view that it is the Non-Ego which yet remains within the sphere of a conscious
Absolute Ego and that it is to be known only practically as the means through
which individual egos can realize themselves morally [a].
The category of Nature gives rise to three Divisions: Mechanics [206ff.], Physics [218ff.], and Organics [260ff.]. From the first we may derive the
categories of Space and Time, Matter and Motion, and Absolute Mechanics. Further deductions can then be made. As for space and time [197-199, 200-02], Hegel, disregarding Kant's 'subjective idealism', considers these to be abstractions, that is,
pure forms, devoid of any kind of determination or character, and as such are
in stark opposition to the 'internality' of mind or thought, that is, Being [b]. "Space and time constitute the idea in and for itself, with space the
real or immediately objective side and time the purely subjective side" [203]. Time in its concept is "like the concept itself generally, eternal, and
therefore absolute presence" [201] . Space and time, he says, disappear and
regenerate in each other, thus constituting motion, a becoming, which is the
"identically existing unity of both", or matter. But this transition from ideality to reality,
from abstraction to concrete existence, a transition from space and time to
reality, appearing as matter, as a given entity, is incomprehensible to the understanding.
These divisions and sub-divisions
represent Hegel's attempt to work through the dialectical process of the
Absolute in Nature, which underlies the concepts, structures, and empirically
observable data of the sciences. He is
thus concerned with a Philosophy of
Nature and not with this or that scientific hypothesis; and with logical
deduction, not with explanation of particulars in terms of efficient causality.
MIND
[III. Philosophy of Spirit]
[5] Although the Absolute or Idea is reflected and manifested in Nature,
the human spirit is required to effect its transition from Nature to existent
Spirit 'in-and-for-itself'. Hegel's treatment of this transition
and the emergence of Absolute existent Spirit constitutes the third part of his
dialectical system.
Division 1 of the Philosophy of Spirit [Encycl. III, 387-482] is the category of (finite
and non-conscious) Subjective Spirit. From
within the Sphere of 'Anthropology' (the soul) Hegel deduces the categories of
the Natural Soul (Physical Qualities, Physical Alterations, Sensibility); the
Feeling Soul (in its Immediacy, Self-feeling, Habit); and the Actual Soul [411]. The Actual Soul is
an organic unity of an 'inner' and an 'outer' aspect, respectively universal
soul and particular body in which the universality is manifested. (Mechanical relationships apply only to
'inert' matter.) It is doubtful that Hegel accepted that the soul
is literally immortal [a]. (In his note to 34 of the Logic he refers to the
pre-Kantian view of the soul as a 'thing' and comments on the ambiguity of this
word. If by this we mean "an immediate existence, something we
represent in sensuous form", then the soul is "in space and sensuously
envisaged"; and we can ask whether it is simple or composite. And he adds that the question is important as
bearing on the soul's immortality, which is supposed to depend on the absence
of composition.)
But the fact is, that in
abstract simplicity we have a category which as little corresponds to the
nature of the soul, as that of compositeness. The actual soul is self-enclosed or
self-contained, possessing self-feeling, sensation, and so on, but lacking
self-consciousness.
The soul's consciousness of itself arises only as a
consequence of its rational awareness of external objects (qua real universals) [424] [b]. This leads to the Sphere of Phenomenology
consciousness in relation to others.
We now have the triad of Consciousness
Proper [418-23] (Sensuous
Consciousness, Sense-Perception, Intellect); Self-Consciousness [424-437] (Appetite/ Instinctive
Desire), 'Self-Consciousness Recognitive', (Universal Self-Consciousness); and
Reason [438]. Hegel here takes up and develops many of the
ideas he had set out in the Phenomenology
of Spirit. He starts with the supposed immediacy and certainty of
sense-apprehension of individual objects. But our knowledge is only of abstractions; all descriptions, even of 'this' are of universals applicable to other
objects. There is thus an emptying of particularity: the 'this' does not exist; there is a
self-contradiction in sense-perception as between the individual and the
universal. The thing then has to be conceived as mediated through
perception as a nexus of universals [c]. Sense-perception in turn gives way to the realm of scientific intellect
(that is, understanding). The intellect
recognises the universal laws (essence) which explain individual phenomena
(appearances) [d]. Appearance is thus reconciled with real
essence; law and phenomenon are identical. In its new phase consciousness becomes self-conscious. Self-consciousness, considered initially as
appetite, seeks to control or appropriate the external object to itself. However, genuine self-consciousness demands that another self be recognised not as an object to be
annihilated but as a self (the 'slave') which will acknowledge the first self's
own selfhood (the 'master')But
such a relationship is inherently unstable, in so far as the slave is thereby
reduced to an unreal thing and therefore cannot provide the master with his
guarantee of freedom. Further, through
labour, doing his master's bidding, the slave "makes himself" and becomes
independent and self-conscious. 'Self-consciousness Recognitive' thereupon leads to universal
self-consciousness, a stage at which mutual recognition of each other's
self-consciousness is achieved. Consciousness and
self-consciousness can then be unified through Reason (Vernunft), which both
enables the subject to recognise the distinction between itself and the object
and yet sees that the distinction lies within itself. The object becomes identity-in-difference [e].
The
Sphere of Psychology [ 440-82] is now attained: this is the
Sphere of Mind (Geist) in itself. Again we have a deduction of three
categories: Theoretical Mind [445-68] (Intuition, Representation
including Recollection, Imagination, and Memory, and Thinking); Practical
Mind [469-80 (Practical Sense Impulses and Choice, Happiness); and Free Mind [481]. As in the case of categories relating to the sciences, Hegel's treatment
here concerns not an empirical discipline of psychology but the dialectical
process, that is, the deduction of the
stages through which the active finite spirit passes. He argues that the free mind (or 'will') arises as the unity of the
theoretical and practical spirit, and exists for itself as free, that is self-determining, self-conscious will as "free
intelligence". In that way
Spirit-in-Itself is identified with Rational Will [f].
ETHICS
[6] [gen 6] [Division 2 of the
Philosophy of Spirit, Encycl. III, 483-552] is the category of Objective Spirit. Inner Subjective Spirit must now pass
over into external objectivity. Within
this category Hegel distinguishes Abstract Right, Morality and Social Ethics,
and within the Sphere of Abstract Right [487-502] he includes Property [488-92], Contract [493-95],
and Wrong (tort and crime) [496-502]. Free and intelligent
individual wills express themselves objectively and universally by utilizing material things and thus come to
'own' them. Property can also be given
up: the thing becomes 'alienated' [a]. But two or more wills can agree to own
property for some common purpose, and this gives rise to the concept of
contract. In so far as a contract can be broken this leads to the
concept of wrong, the 'negation' of which Hegel sees as the concept of
punishment. From this he derives his
dialectical treatment of morality. Punishment being 'external', the opposition of a particular will (as
practical mind) determines itself to harmonize with universal will and thus
becomes moral will [b].
The Sphere of Morality [503-12], is subdivided into Purpose
[504], Intention and Well-Being
[505-6] and Goodness and
Wickedness [507-12]. Morality is grounded in action; and understood 'formally' the moral
will is that which regards itself alone
as the source of its principle of action. But he recognises that everything we do has consequences. These are our 'performances' or 'transactions'
(Handlungen). He reserves the term 'deed' (Tat) to be used in a strict sense for those actions which we will purposefully and whose consequences we
have foreseen. The ends at which we aim, which we intend, and which Hegel sees as
satisfying our human needs, securing our welfare,
have a role to play in morality [c]. However, subjectivity or egoism is transcended in so far as our
particular wills are directed towards the welfare of all, and are identified
with the rational will itself [d]. The good will is thus that which recognises an obligation to conform
its particularity to the universal spirit. Recognition of right and duty, and thereby the good, is guaranteed by conscience [e]. In so far as the will is rational and wills the universal Notion, that
is, the moral or legal law, rather than following desire it is free. Complete realization of its freedom
coincides with the will's objective self-contemplation and thereby brings about the good and happiness (as the will's universal satisfaction). The "absolute purpose of the world" is thus
achieved. At the same time, for
Hegel the universe as a totality is already absolute Good. But in so far as the finite will regards the
world as alien and as constricting, it
sees the good as yet to be
accomplished [f].
POLITICAL/ SOCIAL
PHILOSOPHY
[7] So far, Hegel says, we are confined to
the realm of subjectivity the inner aspect of morality (Moralitt). Now, as action is manifested in the
external world this concept permits a transition to the outer aspect of
morality, that is, customary
or Social Ethics (Sittlichkeit) in
which Abstract Right and Morality can be unified. The Sphere of Social Ethics [513-52] covers the deduction of the
Family [518-22], Civil Society
[523-34], and the State [535-52]. With reference to the respective roles played
by individuals in relation to the family and civil society, Hegel thinks of
these concepts as in opposition. Individuals belong to the family as parts of a unity, while in civil
society they are separate, discrete elements seeking their own satisfaction. The universality of the former concept and the particularity of the
latter are reconciled in the unity-in-difference of the concept of the
'organic' State. The State, as the actualization of the rational self-conscious
will and expressing objective Spirit, is the source of the concept of right and
morality [a]. The individual's duties are determined by his
position in the social organism; and it is in identifying his will with the general will of the state that the
individual actualizes his freedom [b]. And it is the State which provides the framework for the satisfaction of
individual needs and promotes self-realization, though at the same time the
state and its institutions alienate the individual in that they oppose and
constrain him [c]. And he regards this provision as a test of
the suitability or effectiveness of the political constitution of a mature
rational state. But he recognises also
that there are many
possible constitutions, each having developed historically from and therefore
"in identity with" the respective 'spirit' (Volksgeist) of different nations. He is not therefore proposing any utopian or
ideal political structure within which uniquely the moral life can most
perfectly be achieved [d]. Rather he is showing how the history of states can be
understood in terms of the dialectical teleological process of self-actualizing
Spirit. Hence his concern with world-history in which the
Spirit manifests itself as World-Spirit (Weltgeist) through human consciousness [d]. [See also sec. 9.]
ART, RELIGION, AND PHILOSOPHY
[8] [Division 3 of the Philosophy of Spirit, Encycl. III, 553-77]: Absolute
Spirit. With the concept of Absolute Spirit Hegel claims
to have reconciled and brought into a higher synthesis the concepts of
Subjective and Objective Spirit. Spirit, while operating through the finite spirit of national states, is
free from their limitations and recognises its own infinitude. This recognition Absolute Spirit's actualization as self-thinking
Thought is realized through the Spheres of Art, Religion, and Philosophy [a]. However, while at the conceptual dialectical level we can grasp that
there is a successive transition from art to religion to philosophy, Hegel
accepts that different stages of the temporal historical continuum in which the
dialectical process is implicit may not be coincident with it; all three
manifestations of the human spirit may be present simultaneously but in various
stages of development. Accordingly in
his account of the Absolute in all these phases he exhibits the historical
process as well as deducing the logical or conceptual transition from each
stage to the next.
The Sphere
of Art [556-63]. In the context of the
dialectic the Absolute,
Hegel says, is manifested in sensuous
appearance as beauty. His idea of
beauty is called the Ideal, and is the unity of subjectivity (spirit) and
objectivity (matter), as found in the work of art. (Beauty
occurs in Nature too, but he thinks it is superior in art, which is the
immediate creation of Spirit.) Depending
on the relationship of the (ideal) content to the (sensuous) form, different
types of art may be distinguished. If the
sensuous predominates over the content, we have symbolic art (for example, of
India and Egypt); if the spiritual and sensuous elements are found in a
harmonious unity we have Classical art (such as that of the Greeks); while if
the spiritual aspect 'overflows' the sensuous, we have 'romantic' art (the art
of Christendom). And Hegel regards this
last as the highest type in so far as it is in Romantic art that the transition
to the Sphere of Religion is effected. However, considered as art in itself, that is, as judged by aesthetic
standards, Classical art is the perfect
type. Hegel goes on to show that each
type of art is associated with particular arts, though not in a rigid or
mutually exclusive way. Thus,
architecture tends to be characteristic of Symbolic art, sculpture primarily of
Classical art, and poetry, painting, and music (which involve action and
conflict) of Romantic art: but there are
of course Classical and Romantic forms of architecture. Hegel's discussion
of poetry is particularly interesting. He distinguishes between epic poetry (whose principle is objectivity)
and lyrical poetry (subjectivity). Dramatic poetry represents their higher synthesis and is characterized by 'collision'. In tragic drama (Hegel has in mind particularly Greek drama especially
the Antigone) conflicts arise from the opposing but equally justifiable
ethical claims espoused by the characters. In conformity with his dialectic he argues that the antagonists achieve
a kind of reconciliation in death [b]. Comic drama by contrast justifies what has
ethical value through its exposure of worthlessness. Both kinds of drama are said to be unified in
a third type which Hegel calls the 'social play'. With poetry the organic unity of the
'spiritual' and the 'sensuous', which characterizes art, is fractured. Art thereby abolishes itself, and Spirit
moves into the higher Sphere of Religion.
The Sphere of Religion [564-71] is divided into the deducible categories of Religion in General,
'Definite' Religion, and the 'Absolute' Religion which Hegel identifies with
Christianity. He regards this Sphere as
intermediate between the Spheres of Art and Philosophy in that unlike the
former it thinks the Absolute, but it
differs from the latter in so far as what is revealed of the Absolute is through images (Vorstellungen), for example, the notions of creation, God as a
(triune) person, the incarnation, and not through pure concepts. These images are at once sensuous
(particular) and rational (universal). The category of Religion in
General allows a further deduction into three phases of religious
consciousness. (1) God is the universal, infinite,
and only true reality, lacking all differentiation [c]. (2) The finite individual creature sees the
infinite God as set against him: hence
his feelings of being a 'sinner' and alienated. (3) Through religious rituals the union between the finite and the
infinite is restored. Hegel then embarks
on a consideration of the development of particular religions in the various
cultures which have appeared in the course of history (Definite Religion). He distinguishes (a) Religions of Nature,
which involve (i) magic, (ii) a conception of God as 'Substance' ('pantheisms'
such as Chinese religion, Hinduism, Buddhism), and (iii) Religions such as
Zoroastrianism, Syrian, and Egyptian, which he regards as transitional to
(b) the Religions of Spiritual
Individuality, namely Jewish, Greek, and Roman. He then arrives at the third phase of religious consciousness: Christianity, which 'represents' God as both
immanent and transcendent, and man as in union with the Triune God as a
consequence of his incarnation in Christ.
The Sphere of Philosophy [572-7]. Finally Hegel
deduces the third category
of Absolute Spirit Philosophy itself, in which pure conceptual thought of God
as Absolute is made possible [d]. Here we arrive at the culmination of Hegel's system and at the
same time return to the beginning, to the Idea of the Logic, which is
now itself grasped as the manifestation
of the Absolute: "The eternal Idea, in full fruition of its essence,
eternally sets itself to work, engenders and enjoys itself as absolute Mind" [577]. Hegel
sees no incompatibility between Philosophy and Religion; Philosophy completes
Religion, while Religion relates Philosophy to life.
What then of proofs of God's existence?. (1) From the standpoint of the philosophical sphere 'proof'
is the totality of Hegel's own dialectical system. The finite is itself shown to be a
manifestation of Infinite Being, the necessarily existing Absolute Idea. The qualitative distinction between God and
man is thereby eliminated. As he
says [in Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, vol. II, Appendix: 'Proofs for the Existence of God'], the reality or existence (as
Idea), the unity of subject and object, must correspond to the Notion. (This is Hegel's version of the Ontological
Argument.) He does not, however, accept
pantheism and does not 'divinize' Nature [[573] [e]. Certainly Nature in itself in the idea is divine, but it
exhibits no freedom in its existence, only necessity and contingency; and so, in the determinate existence, which makes it nature, is not
to be deified. "As it is, the being of nature does not correspond to
its concept; its existing actuality therefore has no truth; its abstract
essence is the negative, as the ancients conceived of matter in general as the non-ens." But
in so far as Nature is a representation of the Idea, one may admire in it the
wisdom of God" [Encycl. II, 193].
(2) Within the intermediate religious sphere traditional 'proofs' for God's
existence, he says, represent attempts
by reason to support faith and feeling. Necessarily they are inadequate to the extent that they separate the
finite from the infinite, and then try to move from the former to the latter as
different in kind (whereas Being is both finite and infinite) [f]. Nevertheless, they can be seen
legitimately as attempts to articulate that towards which faith is directed [Phil.Rel. III].
PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY
[9] [See Encycl. III, 548-52; also Lectures on the Philosophy
of History] As
we have seen, Hegel alludes to historical development on a number of occasions
in connection with nations,
forms of art, and religions. These are all particular and empirical
manifestations of history in culture. He subdivides history into original history, reflective history, and
philosophical history. From the wider perspective, however, history is the process through
or in which both the Absolute and Infinite Thought unfolds itself dialectically
and (seemingly) inevitably as World-Spirit (Weltgeist) and human thought works
towards [in the Encyclopedia, following his Phenomenology of
Mind] an adequate understanding of the Absolute or [in Philosophy
of History] of freedom knowledge and freedom, for Hegel, being in fact interdependent in that one's freedom consists
in possessing a 'free mind' which reason will then follow [Encycl.II, 481] [a]. With
respect to philosophical history, Hegel stresses that national histories, as phases in the development
of the World-Spirit, can be judged by historians only in terms of the
categories and prejudices of their own cultures and national spirits [b]: complete impartiality is not attainable. Indeed he attempts to trace stages in world history as possessing
characteristic features the despotism of the oriental world, consciousness of
freedom for the few in the Graeco-Roman cultures, the Christian and latterly
the 'Germanic' recognition of human freedom in general. He also argues that "great men" play a
central role in the dialectic of the national spirit of states, though they may not always be aware of it.
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Like Fichte and Schelling,
Hegel was concerned to overcome the dualism bequeathed by Kant. He initially agreed with Schelling that
Fichte had debased Nature by leaving it in the realm of the 'subjective'
creative Ego. He also rejected Fichte's
treatment of Nature as being only the means for man's moral improvement. However, he came to regard Schelling's
approach as equally unsatisfactory. Firstly
he objected to what he supposed to be Schelling's 'divinization' of
Nature. Secondly he was critical of
Schelling's 'identification' of (subjective) Mind and (objective) Nature, the
ideal and the real, as the manifestation of a transcendent Absolute which is
essentially closed to positive conceptualization; an Absolute of total indifference as between the subjective
and objective. As he says [Phenomenology I, 15], this Absolute is
"like the night in which all cows are black" (though some scholars, especially
Bowie, have questioned whether he did in fact have Schelling in mind here).
The essential features of Hegel's own monumental system may be
summarized as follows. The inner essence
of the Absolute as it is 'in itself' is revealed through a progressive
dialectical logic (lacking in Schelling's philosophy). The Infinite Absolute is logically prior to
yet requires finite Nature for its self-expression and self-knowledge as the
Absolute 'for-itself'. Hegel examines
this process in his philosophy of Nature. In Nature we find identity of both necessity-in-freedom and
freedom-in-determinism. Nature is
conceived as a 'fall' from the Absolute and as imperfect and incomplete it is
irrational. Hegel makes it clear that
this is not a scientific hypothesis; his logical deduction is not an
explanation in terms of the concept of causality. For its expression to be fully revealed the
Absolute requires a transition from Nature to Absolute Existent Spirit as
in-and-for-itself. This is effected
through subjective spirit, that is, the human mind. Hegel traces the dialectical development from
human sensation and feeling to consciousness, self-consciousness, universal
self-consciousness, and finally to Reason. The objective spirit is manifested in ethics, such categories as
abstract right, purpose, goodness being duly developed by means of the same
dialectical process. It is in the unity
with or identification of particular wills with the rational will itself that
Hegel discovers the good as the realization of freedom the absolute first
purpose of the world. Inner morality of
course has to be exhibited in the external world, and this outer morality is
dealt with in Hegel's examination of political and social philosophy and of
history. It is in history that the
Absolute Mind manifests itself as World-Spirit national histories being
phases in its development to be judged by historians only in terms of the
categories and prejudices of their own cultures or national spirits. Reconciliation of subjective and objective
spirit is brought about in the higher synthesis of Absolute Spirit. Spirit recognises its own infinitude through
the spheres of Art, Religion and Philosophy in various stages of development
culminating , it is supposed, in Hegel's own philosophical system. In short, Reality as Absolute Reason is revealed objectively in the dialectic
processes of Nature through the reasoning processes of individual human minds
especially the Hegelian philosopher! thereby resolving contradictions
consequent on Kantian dualism.
It can hardly be denied that Hegel's
metaphysical system, which marks the final stage in German Idealism, is an
extraordinary achievement. For the
boldness, breadth, and all-embracing nature of his speculations he must rank as
one of the greatest Western thinkers. And his writings have been enormously influential not least
(positively) on Marx and Sartre, and (negatively) on Schopenhauer and
Kierkegaard, to name but a few philosophers. Nevertheless, his thought has been rejected by most Anglo-American
analytic philosophers. Judged by such
considerations as consistency, correctness of assumptions, validity of
inferences, and the application of his dialectic to concrete situations in
Nature, it has to be granted that there is some substance in their views. (Karl Popper refers to Hegel's "gibberish" and his "bombastic and mystifying
cant"!)
(1) There is a tension between Hegel's dialectical
logic of Being and traditional formal logic in that the articulation of the
former presupposes the latter. To say, for example, that the passing of Being
into not Being is a 'negation' of the concept (Hegel often uses the metaphor of
conflict or struggle to describe such a transition) is on the face of it just
plain wrong. In the case of other
categories the errors seem even more obvious. These are not 'deductions' in the usual logical sense. One can criticize further his view that
through the dialectic deduction of categories thought is a progressive
revelation of the Absolute as ultimate truth, an increasing grasp of the Real
the Real (or Being) is the Rational (as thought), and vice versa. (Indeed it is on this claim that Schelling's
counter-attack was primarily concentrated: he argued that Reason itself could not deduce this identification from within itself. Rather the identity of reality and
rationality as the Absolute is a presupposition of philosophical thought and cannot be fully grasped by reason, which
must start from that which is external to itself, namely, the realm of contingent reality, that is,
being or nature.) Again there is arguably also a conflation here of some
metaphysical sense of truth and truth as a feature of propositions in so far as
they relate to the world or cohere with each other. Nevertheless, Hegel's dialectic as such and
the claims he makes are not meaningless, and should not be dismissed out of
hand. It is often intellectually useful
(though not necessarily correct) to suppose there is change and development in
thought and nature, and that some kind of progress is implicit therein. But
this is a general view, and leads to the next criticism.
(2) There is a lack of coincidence between the
dialectic of the categories and the contingent data of experience, in other
words in the application of Hegel's Logic to Nature. He would say that the dialectic represents an
ideal which, despite frequent oscillation or divergence from it of empirical
events, is in the course of time ever more closely approximated to and revealed
in history and philosophical thought itself.
(3) As in rationalism, we have an assimilation of
causation to logic and reason. This raises the problem of determinism and
historical inevitability.
(4) The problem of the Idea itself. Hegel supposes that the Idea may be identified with God and as freely
positing Nature; Nature is derived from it and thus ontologically
separate. Yet Nature may also be
regarded as the revelation of the Absolute, and inseparable from it: the
infinite is manifested through the finite understood teleologically and in
terms of logical priority. It is
questionable whether these two interpretations are compatible. Arguably Hegel's philosophy and (Christian)
religion coincide, in that the Absolute may be conceived as ultimate thought
and being. Indeed, it is an interesting
consideration whether his philosophy as a whole is final. To be consistent his system must presumably
allow for further development, though it is difficult to see quite what form
this might take, given that the ultimate category has allegedly been 'deduced'. The 'left' Hegelians certainly interpreted
his philosophy as being incomplete, and regarded it as incompatible with
Christianity and such ideas as personal immortality of the soul. Indeed the initial pantheism of his 'left'
followers were soon replaced by the more radical atheism of Feuerbach and Marx.
(Stace [p. 514] is of the opinion that Hegel did not take immortality
literally, "but regarded it as a Vorstellung for the infinitude of
spirit and the absolute value of spiritual individuality. Immortality is a present quality of the
spirit, not a future fact or event.") The 'right' Hegelians, however, tended to regard Protestant Christianity
and the Prussian State as the apotheosis of Hegelian thought.
(5) Popper is highly critical both of Hegel's
"Platonizing worship of the state", [a] which he sees as a link between
Platonism and modern totalitarianism, and of his dialectic and historicist philosophy.
Hegel: Phnomenologie des Geistes (1807)
(Phenomenology of Mind); Wissenschaft
der Logik (vol. I, 1812/3; vol. II, 1816) (Science of Logic); Encyklopdie der philosophischen
Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1817; 2nd enlarged edn, 1827) (Encyclopedia
of the Philosophical Sciences in Outline); Naturrecht und
Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse (1821; 2nd edn Grundlinien
der Philosophie des Rechts, 1833) (Philosophy of Right) Good recent translations of the Phenomenology
of Spirit [Mind] and the Science of Logic are those of A. V.
Miller. For the Encyclopedia see [Part I] The Logic of Hegel, trans. W. Wallace, foreword by J.
N. Findlay; [Part II] Hegel's Philosophy of Nature; and [Part III] The
Philosophy of Mind, both trans. A. V. Miller). See Bibliography for other translations and details of his
posthumously published lectures on Aesthetics, the Philosophy of History,
Religion, and the History of Philosophy.
Studies:
Introductions
R. Norman, Hegel's
Phenomenology.
P. Singer, Hegel.
W. T.
Stace, The Philosophy of Hegel.
Advanced (of many)
J. N. Findlay, Hegel: A Re-examination.
K. R. Popper, The Open Society and its Enemies, vol.
2: Hegel and Marx.
M. Rosen, Hegel's
Dialectic and its Criticism.
H. Solomon, In the
Spirit of Hegel: A Study of Hegel's
Phenomenology.
C.
Taylor, Hegel.
Collections of
essays
K. Ameriks (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to German Idealism.
F. Beiser (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Hegel.
CONNECTIONS
Hegel
Metaphysics/ methodology
Note: Hegel's philosophy as a whole was rejected as 'negative' philosophy
by Schelling in his last period. Hegel
equally rejected Schelling's 'positive' philosophy [see Schelling sec. 6]. Hegel's rationalistic or speculative idealism [e.g., sec. 1] was also
rejected by Schopenhauer [see secs 1, 2, &
3]; by Kierkegaard [see sec. 1], and by Nietzsche [see sec. 2] the
entries below are representative.
[2b; see also 3a-d] |
Understanding grasps 'static' concepts but dynamic Reason needed to transcend oppositions and grasp dialectic of category transformation (triadic); negation and determination |
Kant→
Fichte→
→Schelling→
→Peirce
→Bradley
→Sartre
|
[2c 3a]
[2a]
[2b 3c]
[1e g 3a]
[3b]
[2b]
|
[2c] |
Truth as coherence;
degrees of truth and reality; the categories develop from each other hierarchically, so the Absolute is implicit |
Leibniz
→Bradley
→Royce
→Dewey |
[4d]
[1c 5c 6a]
[1c]
[2c] |
[3b] |
Doctrine
of Being: Being and Non-Being
resolved in Becoming;
category of Being-for-self |
→Sartre |
[2b c 2b] |
[3c; cf. 5c] |
Actuality as
synthesis of Essence and Appearance; Matter
and Form; actuality generates Cause and Effect, and Reciprocity; Essence and Being resolved in category of Notion |
Aristotle→
Kant→
→Schelling→ |
[13c 14a]
[3e]
[2b] |
[3d; cf. 1c 2c; see also 8c e] |
Category of Notion: (subjective aspect) formal logic; (objective aspect) categories of concept of Nature; both aspects ultimately synthesized into Absolute Idea the unity of Life
and Cognition, and all truth, "the thought of thought" |
Aristotle→
Fichte→
→Dilthey
→Dewey |
[12e]
[1b 2a]
[1b]
[2c] |
[4a; cf. 1c 5f 6a] |
Philosophy
of Nature: Absolute considered 'for-itself'
(self-alienated Spirit); Nature as 'fall' from the Idea; Nature is both necessity-in-contingency and freedom-in-determinism, and manifestation of rational Spirit |
Plato
Kant→
Fichte→
→Schelling→
→Peirce |
[sec. 5]
[5c]
[1b 2c]
[1c 3c 4d 6b 6c]
[3a] |
Mind |
[5a; cf. 1c 6f 7b] |
Philosophy
of Spirit trans ition to Absolute considered in-and-for-itself: 'actual' soul as organic unity of universal soul and particular body; soul may not be immortal? |
Kant→
Fichte→
→Schelling→
→Marx
→Nietzsche |
[3b 5a b]
[1b 3c]
[1b]
[2a]
[2a] |
[5d] |
Scientific intellect
discovers real universal laws which explain individual phenomena |
Kant→
→Schelling→ |
[2c 3e]
[2b] |
[6a; cf. 4a] |
Spirit
expressed through utilization of material things by free wills; alienation of property |
→Schelling→
→Marx |
[4a]
[1c] |
[6b] |
Wrong as breach of
contract; negation of this is punishment; harmonization of particular will with universal will → moral will |
Rousseau→
Kant→
Bentham |
[1g]
[6c]
[1f] |
[6c; cf. 6f] |
Morality grounded in action; (formally) moral will as source of principle of action, but ethics concerned also with ends (satisfying needs) |
Kant→
Fichte→
→Peirce
→Dewey
|
[6b-e]
[3a b]
[4a]
[3c]
|
[6d] |
Particular will
directed towards
welfare of all (egoism transcended) identified with rational will |
Kant→
→Peirce
→Nietzsche
Bradley
Royce |
[6f]
[4a]
[1b 2a]
[7g]
[2c] |
[6f; cf. 6c 7b] |
Free action from
rational moral will rather than desire; realization of freedom and the achievement of the good and the will's happiness in objective self-contemplation; evil as real but universe perfect and Good accomplished (absolute purpose of world) |
Kant→
Fichte→
→Schelling→
→Schopenhauer
→Peirce
→Bradley
→Royce
→Dewey
→Santayana |
[6a 6b-e 8a]
[3a]
[6d]
[3a]
[4a]
[7h]
[1b 2g]
[3b c]
[6a] |
Political philosophy |
[7a] |
The 'organic' State
as actualization
of self-conscious will; source of concept of abstract right and morality (reconciled in Sittlichkeit: individuals, family, society, and state) |
Rousseau→
Fichte→
→Schelling→
→Marx
→Spencer
→Nietzsche
→Royce
→Dewey
→Ricoeur |
[1h]
[4b
d]
[4b]
[2b 2d 2e]
[2a]
[4a]
[2c]
[3b]
[10d e] |
[7d CSa; see further 9a] |
No utopian or ideal political structure; many different constitutions
can provide framework for
the moral life [Hegel as a totalitarian?] |
Plato→
→Marx
→Dewey
→Popper |
[sec. 14]
[2e]
[5b]
[3a c] |
[8e] |
(In philosophical
sphere) Hegel's own dialectical system is proof for existence of God (his version of the ontological
argument); qualitative distinction between God and man eliminated but pantheism/ divination of Nature rejected |
Spinoza→
Kant→
→Schelling→
→Kierkegaard |
[2b 2c]
[2c 5d]
[6a]
[1a b f] |
[8f] |
(In religious
sphere) traditional proofs as attempts to support faith and feeling; invalid because they first separate the finite from the and infinite |
Kant→
Fichte→
→Schelling→
→Kierkegaard |
[5d]
[5b]
[6e]
[1b] |