FICHTE
(1762 1814)
ETHICAL
IDEALISM
Johann Fichte was the
eldest child of a ribbon maker. He was
born in Rammenau, Lusatia (Germany) and educated at the famous Pforta School
(through the generosity of a baron who had become impressed by his potential),
and then at the Universities of Jena, Wittenberg, and Leipzig, studying
theology and philosophy. Financially
insecure he became a private tutor in 1788 but in 1794 he secured a
professorship at Jena as a result of the recommendations of Kant and
Goethe. However, his unorthodox views
and teaching methods eventually led to his dismissal in 1799. He taught for a short time at Erlangen and
Königsberg, and then at Berlin (where he was briefly Rector). He was active in the struggle against
Napoleon, but he devoted most of the remainder of his life to his writing. He died in Berlin of typhus.
METAPHYSICS
[1] [See The
Doctrine of Knowledge.] Fichte's
metaphysics is closely connected with his theory of knowledge, ethics, and
philosophy of religion. For convenience
these several areas will be examined separately. His system arises out of a negative and a
positive reaction to Kant. Fichte rejected the idea of an
unknowable 'thing-in-itself'; this, he said, leads to dogmatic
materialism and determinism. But he was aware of himself as a
free, moral being, with an interest in the self rather than in 'things',
and understood this as the active, free,
Absolute Ego, which is self-affirming intelligence-in-itself, creative thought,
and the Absolute moral principle in man. We cannot of course experience this transcendental or pure Ego; it is not an
object of consciousness, or indeed a substantial entity at all, but its
positing and limiting of itself in the finite ego or individual self is a
precondition for the emergence of unified consciousness. It is thus the universal 'I' principle which
is active within all consciousnesses. And Fichte claims we
have an 'intellectual intuition' of it within the consciousness, and that it is
implicit in our actions. He identifies
it with a 'doing' (Tun) or activity [a], but this is not an active 'thing' (ein Ttiges). He adopted this as his immediately basic
proposition to constitute the certain foundation of his 'doctrine (or theory)
of knowledge' [see sec. 2].
Fichte was faced with two problems: how to derive 'objective' consciousness from
the self-conscious intelligence-in-itself, and how to account for the world of
material objects. His answer to these is
his 'phenomenology of consciousness'. He distinguishes three principles or
stages. By reflecting on its own consciousness self-determining
reason 'deduces' real categories. (1) The pure Ego posits itself. Its positing of itself in intuition
constitutes its 'being'; and we refer to this under the category of reality. (2) Now to
posit itself as pure or Absolute Ego it must be opposed by a general
objectivity: a 'Non-Ego' is 'opposited' to it. Here the category of negation is applicable. It gives rise to, and is a precondition for
what he says is the unlimited activity or striving, and moral self-realization
of the Absolute Ego. (3) The
Ego and the Non-Ego must limit or restrain each other; for if they were
unlimited they would cancel each other out and there would be no consciousness
at all. We thus reach the category of limitation or finitude. The Ego posits a limited (finite, or divisible) empirical and individual ego in opposition to the limited Non-Ego. This philosophical reconstructing is regarded by Fichte as a practical deduction, in so far as the Absolute Ego, in its positing or determining of
the Non-Ego, produces Nature as the ground of ideal actions (involving desire,
free choice, and self-activity) [see his System of Ethics]. However, if we think of the Absolute,
pure Ego as positing itself and as
being limited or determined by the Non-Ego, the deduction is a theoretical one; and it is concerned
with 'real' sequences of actions involving, for example, 'ideas' (Vorstellungen) and sensations, but the
Non-Ego remains in the realm of consciousness. Fichte stresses that the theoretical deduction is subordinate to the
practical [b][b] in that the spiritual Ego
strives to realize itself (the 'end') in
unlimited activity using the Non-Ego as its 'means'. [See further in sec. 2.]
Fichte also considers formal logic as derivable from philosophy the fundamental
'science' [c]. [See Foundation of the Entire Doctrine of Knowledge.] Although the
laws of general logic in a sense determine how our 'deed-acts' or 'doings' are to be thought, the basic
propositions of philosophy are prior to
their formalizations in logic. Fichte
identifies a corresponding three stage deduction. Firstly, the certainty of the identity 'A =
A' exhibits the Ego's positing of itself as identical to itself through its
pure activity. (This is the 'absolutely
unconditioned fundamental principle'.) Secondly, he derives the 'proposition of oppositing', ' A is not A',
(the conditioned fundamental principle 'with regard to content') which
corresponds to the absolute oppositing of the Non-Ego to the Ego. Lastly, he deduces the third fundamental principle (conditioned in its
form): 'A (in part) = A, and A (in part) = A', which grounds the oppositing of the finite or
divisible Non-Ego to a finite Ego.
KNOWLEDGE
[2] In his Doctrine of Knowledge Fichte rejects
'dogmatism' [a], according to which
consciousness is explained in terms of the empirical realm and mechanical
necessity. So in his theory of knowledge he attempts to reconcile our ordinary experience of
things in the world with his idealist metaphysics. It consists essentially in an examination of
the process of theoretical deduction and its explanation in terms of the
practical deduction. There are three
stages in the theoretical deduction. Firstly the Absolute Ego produces the forms of intuition of space
and time as a result of its "power of
productive imagination". The Ego
is both passive and active. It is
passive in its reception of sensation which give rise to 'subjective
modifications' of itself representations (Vorstellungen)
and images (Bilder); and active in so
far as it refers sensations to the Non-Ego. Secondly, the understanding (Verstand), through the 'power of judgement' 'fixes' these
representations as concepts and then as objects of thought for the understanding. Lastly, through the
'power of absolute abstraction' (reason),
the universal is abstracted from particular objects (the Non-Ego), thereby
enabling us to reflect on the pure
Ego and its productive activity, and thus to expand our
self-consciousness. At each stage of
this progressive movement from sensation, to space and time, and the categories
the lower is apprehended and articulated more fully and clearly by the reason [a], but Fichte says that a complete or pure
intellectual intuition is never attained. He then tries to show how the theoretical deduction itself has to be
referred back to and underpinned by the practical
deduction. Implicit in the Absolute Ego as unlimited striving
is a subconscious drive (Trieb), which both exists for the
limited empirical Ego as feeling (Gefhl) and constrains it because the
Non-Ego is opposing it. This drive then becomes what he
calls "an impulse towards the object"
and is experienced as force (Kraft) [b]. The impulse, initially experienced as a
primitive level of reflection, comes to
manifest itself more clearly in distinct desires and acquires more
'satisfactions' through the striving a striving which can be satisfied,
albeit only partially, through moral action. So what Fichte appears to be saying is that the world of appearances, that is, of 'ideas' (Vorstellungen), is qua Nature the manifestation of the objective spiritual reality (which is independent of finite egos and
identifiable with the Absolute or unlimited Ego). As deduced theoretically it is
consciousness: deduced practically it is
passive, 'dead' Nature knowable only through the individual, empirical ego's
moral striving for perfection. Knowledge
for Fichte is thus essentially practical [c][c]. It seems to follow also that, (1) given his account of the categories
(which in Kant's philosophy belong to the transcendental logic) as belonging to
the 'self-oppositing' of the Absolute Ego rather than as transcendentally
'subjective' forms of the individual understanding, and (2) his view that
formal logic is grounded in the Doctrine
of Knowledge, the distinction between a
priori and a posteriori knowledge
'breaks down' [d]. [Or, rather, perhaps we may say that our
experience of things derives from the individual self-consciousness but that
both the natural world and individual consciousness are the products of the
Absolute Ego's self-positing. Our
knowledge of this 'universal Ego' (allgemeinen
Ich) is thus at once a priori (with respect to ground) and a posteriori (with respect to content experienced in act). However, this interpretation remains contentious.]
ETHICS/ PHILOSOPHY OF MAN
[3] [See The System of Ethics.] If Fichte's
metaphysics and theory of knowledge are grounded in the practical realm, what
is the basis of his ethics itself? He
sees man as a unity of
conscious active being. But the
fundamental impulse of striving is, as it were, two-dimensional. On the one hand man is an object,
governed by the laws of sense-intuition, determined by nature, concerned with
meeting his biological needs, in particular, self-preservation. On the other hand, as self-determining subject, or pure spirit, man exhibits a
drive to freedom and independence. Freedom, however, is possible in
both realms. Man is formally free in so far as he consciously reflects and chooses to follow his
natural impulse. He is materially free if he acts for the
sake of freedom, so as to achieve the Ego's independence, or
self-realization. Fichte argues that a synthesis is needed,
and this can be attained if the former renounces pleasure and the latter its
'purity', that is, its independence from natural objects. He also claims that freedom is inseparable from, and indeed in a sense
identical with law [a], in that we cannot
think of ourselves as free without at the same time thinking of ourselves as
falling under a law, and vice versa. He
sets out the central tenets of his ethics on the basis of this account of
freedom and law.
The
objective world of Nature posited by the Absolute Ego is to be seen, not
just as bringing about self-consciousness and as the means for ensuring our
self-preservation and material welfare, but also as necessary for us to fulfil ourselves morally, so that
we might achieve our end as spiritual, rational self-determining agents through the utilization of external objects. It is by virtue of
its role in facilitating the creative expression of the inner spirit and
self-realization of the will that labour acquires dignity [b]. A key concept in Fichte's ethics is that of conscience, "the immediate consciousness
or feeling of our determinate duty". He equates this with a formal condition to which moral actions must
conform: "Act always according to your
best conviction of your duty". And it is in this feeling that
reconciliation between the (objective) empirical Ego and the (subjective) pure
Ego can be effected and harmony achieved [c]. Conscience is infallible; and if we are
immediately conscious of our duty we are obliged to do it. But Fichte recognises that its precise
application to a particular course of action may not always be clear; and
indeed we may ourselves often be responsible for obscuring our own
conscience. In such cases, if we do not
act impulsively, we should act so as to maximize self-advantage. The philosopher's job is to deduce and set
out general rules for action and to categorize them according as to whether
they are conducive or not to the Ego's moral end. But the determination of one's actual
obligation in a particular situation remains a matter for the individual
conscience. Failure to attend to the call of duty, backsliding
or laziness on the part of the empirical ego constitutes evil [d].
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
[4] [The System of Ethics; The Foundation of Natural Right.] We exist in a
context of constraint. There can be no
self-consciousness unless the finite individual Ego can be set off against
other similar Egos. And to act in any
way presupposes a common
sensible and unique social and cultural world in which our action can occur. Members of a community of rational beings
necessarily constrain each other. As
Fichte says, our freedom
is limited in so far as we recognise the freedom of others. He expresses this formally in his 'Rule of Right' [a], which provides the justification for
private property, public expression of opinion, and so on. To reconcile the equal claims of all members
of the community to such rights he says that individual wills have to be 'united' to become one General Will. Fichte regards the State as the
'super-sensible' structure and agent through which this can be articulated and
the rights and freedom of its members thereby guaranteed and their
self-realization made possible (and thence the self-realization of the Absolute
Ego). To establish this State
individuals enter into a social contract [b].
As to the kind of state he advocates, he rejects both despotism and democracy (in
the sense of rule by the people which he thinks leads to chaos). But within these extremes a range of
constitutions may be compatible with the concept of the rational state. He seems to have favoured a kind of
collective ombudsman (he calls it the 'Ephorate') to check any abuse
of power. Such a collective or
oligarchy, however, is to possess neither legislative nor executive functions [c]. He envisages a planned economy
and division of labour so as to encourage material, social, and spiritual
self-realization. But once all the
members of the community have acquired moral perfection the State will no
longer have a purpose and will cease to exist [d]. Fichte also
anticipates that the idea of the general Will can be extended to cover all
mankind in a federation of nations; and, ironically, he supposed that the
German nation might be the pacesetter towards this ultimate unification. [See Natural
Right.]
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION
[5] Fichte did not have a fixed position on
religion; his views were constantly being modified. Initially [The Foundation of our Belief in a Divine Providence] he tended
towards a kind of Spinozistic pantheism
(but which was regarded by many contemporaries as atheism). Considered from the standpoint of ordinary
consciousness or from empirical science, there can be no place for a divine
intelligence; the Absolute Being is the world. At the same time we think
('transcendentally') of the world as 'opposited' by the Absolute Being or
Ego. However, this gives rise to a
dilemma. Is the Absolute Ego a being
prior to Nature which posits it as a totality of individual Egos? Or is it a manifestation of the subconscious
strivings of individuals, acting only in and through them? In general Fichte seems to regard the Absolute as the One Life which intuits the objects of the material world. This
might perhaps be identified with God as the active ordering process or living moral order (the ordo ordinans), to which the Ego belongs the Non-Ego, the world (ordo ordinata) being the means by which
the Ego can achieve its satisfaction for its striving. However, we cannot attribute personality or substantiality to such
a being. Any attempt to describe
it would condition it and render it dependent. All we can do, Fichte says [The
Vocation of Man], is to think of the
One Life or 'active ordering' as the infinite creative Reason or eternal Will [a], by which everything exists as 'presentations' and in which it becomes conscious
of itself. Whether as moral order or infinite Will 'God' must remain
an object of faith (manifested in action) and not knowledge [b]. In later works
[for example, The Doctrine of Religion]
Fichte emphasized the transcendence, and self-subsistence of Absolute Being, while maintaining its identification with the one
infinite, eternal 'Life'. This Being knows itself absolutely (as object) through
its external expression (its Dasein,
or 'being there') in consciousness and thus through the individual
consciousnesses (as subjects) of rational individuals (though they themselves
cannot grasp the totality). An
alternative view was also offered at about the same time [in his 1804 lectures
on the Theory of Science], according
to which the Absolute is
Light and its essence Being and Thought [c], an
apparent division between which is exhibited only in Light's radiation.
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Fichte's philosophy
can readily be understood as a response
to Kant's. Arguing that Kant cannot
consistently claim even that there is a thing-in-itself, a noumenon, Fichte asserts, nevertheless, that is knowable
through practical reason as the unlimited Absolute Ego or Being. The central thrust of his thinking is
therefore towards an ethical idealism. In effect he subordinates Kant's first Critique to the second, restricts the scope of cognition, and
synthesizes 'subject' and 'object'. Indeed in his identification of 'feeling' or conscience with the 'formal
condition' of duty he may be supposed to have made an advance on Kant's
categorical imperative. Against this, it
can be argued that it does not bring about the harmonization of the subjective
and objective Egos as he supposes. Furthermore, one can question whether the tension between the
theoretical and practical deductions can be sustained. The self-positing pure Ego is supposed to
utilize the Non-Ego as its means (in the primacy of the practical) while at the
level of the theoretical it is conceived of as being limited or determined by
the Non-Ego. Arguably the dualism
between consciousness and 'dead' Nature has not been satisfactorily
resolved. And it is questionable whether
Fichte's claim that conscience is infallible is tenable given his wish (with
Kant) to exclude all considerations of heteronomy in moral judgements. Moreover, in the context of German Idealism,
Fichte's system has been held to be one-sided. Criticisms have also be levelled against the religious aspect of his
thought. It has been said that the
various stages of development of his ideas are not always consistent. While his early views led to the charge of
atheism, his later metaphysical accounts of God as Absolute being or as 'Light'
have been seen as evidence of a sharp break with his ethical idealism. Fichte himself would seem to have regarded
the latter as 'being' implicit in and presupposing the divine Absolute Being.
Fichte: ber den
Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre (1794; 1798) (Concerning the Concept of
the Doctrine of Knowledge; trans. D. Breazeale); Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre,
(1794/5; 1802) (Foundation of the Entire Doctrine of Science; trans. P.
Heath); Grundlage des Naturrechts (1796/7) (The Foundation of Natural
Right; ed. F. Neuhouser, trans. M. Bauer); Das System der Sittenlehre
nach den Principien der Wissenschaftslehre (1798) (The System of Ethics
based on the Doctrine of Science; ed. & trans. G. Zller & D.
Breazeale); ber den Grund unseres Glaubens an eine göttliche Weltregierung (1798)
(Concerning the Ground of Our Belief in a Divine World-Order; trans. D. Breazeale); Die Bestimmung des
Menschen (1800) (The Vocation of Man; trans. P. Preuss); Die
Religionslehre (1806) (The Doctrine of Religion; trans. W.
Smith). See also the collection of extracts from Fichte
in R. Bubnner (ed.), German Idealist Philosophy.
Studies
R. Adamson, Fichte.
F. Neuhouser, Fichte's
Theory of Subjectivity.
E. B. Talbot, The Fundamental Principle of Fichte's
Philosophy.
Collections of essays
K.
Ameriks (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism.
D. Breazeale and T. Rockmore (eds), New Essays on Fichte's later
Jena 'Wissenschaftslehre'.
G. Zöller (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Fichte.
CONNECTIONS
Fichte