HUSSERL
(1859 1938)
PHENOMENOLOGY
Edmund Husserl was
born into a Jewish family in Prosnitz, Moravia. He was educated at the Gymnasium in Olmitz and then studied physics,
mathematics, astronomy, and philosophy at the Universities of Leipzig, Berlin,
and Vienna. After gaining his doctorate
in 1882 he studied further in Vienna under Brentano, subsequently becoming a Privatdozent at Halle. From 1906-16 he was ausserordentlicher professor at Göttingen, where he established the
Phenomenological movement (though his relationships with his colleagues were
often strained). He moved to Freiburg as
full professor in 1916 and remained there until his death, having retired from
teaching in 1928.
ONTOLOGY AND METHOD
[1] [gen 1] Two preliminary points should be made. (1) Husserl was not a systematic philosopher
in the sense that he sought to construct a system after the manner of, say, the
German idealists. But closely integrated
with his epistemology and his philosophy
of language there is a carefully worked out ontology grounded not in vacuous
speculation but as he saw it firmly rooted in experience. (2) His philosophy was always undergoing
development. As he himself put it, "I am
a perpetual beginner". But while his
thought often seems to have passed through a number of stages, much recent
scholarship has tended to show that many of the ideas supposedly introduced in
his later writings were present, implicitly if not explicitly, in early work.
Husserl's phenomenology grew out of his
early attempts to analyse and clarify the concepts of mathematics and logic [see Logical Investigations I, 1st edn]. He initially espoused a 'psychologistic' approach, but he gradually
came to reject this and instead held the view that statements of mathematics and logic are necessary
truths, associated with deductive inference, and constituting an a priori 'science' (Wissenschaft), that is, field of knowledge; whereas statements of
psychology are concerned with facts or events, are causal or probable, and
grounded in inductive arguments [a]. Mathematics as a formal
axiomatic system is part of formal or symbolic logic, but both together belong to 'pure logic', by
which he understood a systematic
structure of laws and theories grounded in quasi-Platonic ideal categories of meaning [b]. This concept is closely connected with that of intentionality, by
which he meant approximately 'directedness'. Husserl said that the
experiences of our mental life (perceiving, imagining, judging, and so on) are
episodic acts of consciousness, mental or cognitive acts. Such acts both have a 'content' and are
'intentional' in the sense that they 'intend', are directed towards some
'object' [c],
even if in some instances, such as hallucinations, there is no external
object. (Similarly physical actions can
be intentional.) Husserl regarded
intentionality as constituting a relation between the subjective agent and the
object and also supposed it to be a kind of function or quality of the agent's
act to perceive, imagine, and so on, in a particular way. Initially he distinguished between the intended object, that is,
the referent, or what we 'mean', and the content of the mental act in
effect its 'sense' (though he said that Sinn and Bedeutung in German are actually synonyms) [LI, 13]. Entities which have referents are
expressions, and these include names and sentences. The referents of sentences
are 'states-of-affairs'. And he
argues (i) that expressions can have
different senses and yet refer to the same object, and (ii) that a give word
with the same sense can refer to different referents. He made a further distinction between the
real content and the ideal content. The 'real' content consists
of 'matter' (that which makes the act a
presentation [Vorstellung]) and
'quality' (that which makes the act a certain type such as a judgement, or a
question). The 'ideal' content, however, is a 'species', an ideal entity, of
which, Husserl says, the real content is an instantiation [d]. (In the
intentional mode of 'signifying', logic and mathematics are concerned with
special sorts of meanings 'ideal singulars', which include 'nominal' meanings
as objects of acts of presentation, 'sentential' meanings, and 'states of
affairs' intended by acts of judgement.)
[2] Underlying this early account of
language and mental acts is a commitment to an ontology (what there 'is'). And throughout the first decade of the
twentieth Husserl was seeking to develop a general 'realist' 'transcendental phenomenology' which (1) would comprehend all aspects
or modes of conscious experience; (2) would thereby reveal a formal ontology of
fundamental categories; and (3) would constitute "philosophy as rigorous science" [see the essay of
this title]. Such a 'science' would facilitate the placing of
both the natural and the human sciences on a firm basis, under the unifying
category of the understanding [a], which would take account of the
constitutive and explicative role played by 'subjectivity' in our experience
while avoiding the errors of other contemporary approaches to philosophy. Thus he attacked (1) materialism and reductionalist phenomenalism (the
analysis of physical objects exclusively in terms of sensory impressions and
ideas, and not to be confused with his own method of reduction); (2) 'scientist' theories, such as
positivism and naturalism, which take it for granted that there is an
objective world but fail to ask the question whether knowledge of it is
possible, and which, Husserl argued, lead to scepticism; (3) 'historicism', which had
originally impressed him but which he now found to be inconsistent in that
cultural relativists assumed the existence of absolute truths in the very
process of denying them. (4) speculative idealism and
generally irrationalist philosophies [b].
To achieve his ideal of 'scientific
rigour' in his phenomenology Husserl
combined his account of intentionality with what he called the method of transcendental-phenomenological reduction [see Idea of Phenomenology and Ideas I]. This method was grounded in the activity of 'bracketing'
(epoché) [first worked out in
1905; see Ideas I, 27]. In a non-reflective mode we accept our mental
experiences as relating to, or being about the world. However, we can reflect philosophically and
raise the question whether or not these objects which we 'intend' and suppose
to exist actually do exist. In bracketing our experiences we
suspend belief in the actual existence of intended objects be they physical
objects, persons, minds, propositions, or meanings. (This is not,
however, intrinsically a 'sceptical' position) [c]. We are thus led
back ('re-duced') to the intrinsic experiences themselves. This is what Husserl means when he says he
wants to get "to the things themselves" (zu
den Sachen selbst) a 'thing' being an intuition (Anschauung),
namely, that which is immediately given to us in experience, be it sensory or
otherwise, as a consequence of which we can see what the designating word or
expression for the thing actually signifies [see, for example, Logical Investgns,
I, ch. 2, 21; see also II, part 1, passim]. Through an imaginative consideration or intuition of how appearances of
things might be varied we can then come to discover 'eidetically' their
'invariant general structures', that is, the essences (Wesen) of
things. Intuition for Husserl is a kind
of non-empirical pure seeing not like the seeing or perceiving of
physical objects but more like the gaining of insight into or apprehension of what is directly
given to thought in a mental act [d]. A description of both these
structures and the consciousness which 'intends' them can then be
attempted. Husserl's rigorous phenomenological philosophy is thus an
eidetic science; and while descriptive it is not to be thought of as a
descriptive psychology which is concerned with cognitive processes as such [e]. But in Cartesian Meditations [39-40] he in fact talks of it as a "phenomenology of genesis through which
[alone] the ego becomes understandable", the problems of phenomenology being
reduced to the title "the (static and genetic) constitution of objectivities of
possible consciousness".
[3] Husserl's ontology, initially set out in
the Logical Investigations and then in Ideas I, was more systematically developed in Ideas II and III. He distinguished three realms: of Essence, Fact, and Meaning.
(1) The realm of Essence. This is a realm of 'ideal' entities, which
are necessary, non-spatial and
non-temporal. This realm contains
formal essences and material essences [a]. The study of formal essences is the field of
formal ontology; and this applies to formal essences or categories of all
objects or entities constituting the world individuals, properties, states of
affairs, events, as well as linking categories such as truth and identity. Together with formal logic,
which is concerned with linguistic categories (name, predicate, statement, for
example) and meaning categories (concepts, propositions), formal ontology makes
up Husserl's Logic in a wide sense as a unifying science of interconnected
necessary truths [b]. Material essences belong to the field of material ontology. And both formal and material ontology, as well
as mathematics and logic, are what Husserl calls the eidetic sciences. Material
essences are allocated to three regions Nature, Living-World (Spirit, Geist, Humanity), and Consciousness
(each of which of course has its own formal essence). These regions are the highest genera in
Husserl's structure: they contain
species and sub-species in hierarchical dependence. Thus, Nature as the highest material species
contains the essences Material Thing, Plant, Animal; humanity contains the
species of Cultural Entities, for example, ideas, values, books, works of art,
and so on, as well as of course human persons; while Consciousness includes
such species as Perception, Belief,
Judgement, Imagination.
(2) The realm of Fact of
concreteness, spatiality and temporality [c]. Each and all of the essences are, according to Husserl, instantiated in
this realm as (a) individuals (which are made up of instances of species, qualities, relations all these
being dependent entities which he calls moments); (b) states-of-affairs; (c) events and experiences [c]. Whereas essences belong to the ideal
realm, instantiations are concrete. All
form the subject matter of the empirical sciences: physics, chemistry, and biology study Nature;
the social sciences deal with the Human or Living-World; while phenomenology is
the science of Consciousness and
Intentionality. A given human individual can be investigated within Nature by reference (a) to its physical body
and soul moments; (b) within
the region of Living-World in terms of its Living Body and Human 'I
moments'; while (c) in the region of Consciousness the 'self' can be treated
phenomenologically as the 'Pure I' or Transcendental Ego [d].
(3) The Realm of Meaning (Sinn) [e]. Belonging to this realm (which, like the realm of essences, is ideal)
are the contents of intentional experiences or acts. These are the subject matter of phenomenological
reflection. They include the 'senses' of
all essences individuals, predicational senses of species, qualities,
relations; and also propositions and senses of states-of-affairs. Husserl makes it clear that meanings or senses are not
themselves essences; they exist rather, it would seem, as a function of human
consciousness interacting with raw matter (hyle)
and the realm of essences. They
have some kind of reality and are regarded as temporal but non-spatial. In this later stage of Husserl's thought meanings or 'senses' (Sinne) are no longer considered as
species [see sec. 1d] but
as contents of intentional acts of consciousness; and this includes both
linguistic and non-linguistic acts. Already [Lectures 1908] he had distinguished between the noesis, or noetic 'moment' of an act,
and its noema. The noesis is what he had
previously termed the real content. The noema is the intentional content [e], that
is, not the abstract object which we suppose to be the real object of
intentionality but the 'object-as-intended meant precisely as meant'.
Intentional objects, in addition to having sense, are also accorded a 'thetic'
aspect which determines what type of experience it is whether perceptual,
judgemental, orectic (that is, appertaining to desire), and so on.
[4] In his later work [Cartesian Meditations and Crisis of European Sciences] he
modified his phenomenological
method further. While formerly it
was a description of a separate realm of being [see sec 2] he
now regarded it as a
reflection and description of what he called criteria for the 'coherence' of
our experiences. Knowledge of
these criteria gives us a further condition for the definition of 'phenomenon'
and the making of statements about phenomena understood by reference to the
'appropriateness' of intentional acts,
that is, whether it is congruous to perform certain kinds of actions in a
particular situation (putting food out for a god, for example), or to believe
certain sorts of statements (they may be non-sensical). In general it is an
empirical matter to determine whether purposive actions or acts about
intentional objects are or are not adequate. But Husserl also says that
although individual acts may be coherent they may not collectively constitute a
coherent series in that a given action or belief may occur in a different
context from another in the sequence. So
he now suggests that a further job of phenomenology is to undertake an 'intentional
analysis' to clarify the relations between acts; and he sees this as being
revealed through what he calls 'horizons' of intentional acts. If a statement can provide a criterion of
coherence in this way, then it is a statement about a phenomenon or phenomena. Phenomenology thus ceases to be
concerned with providing foundations for the various mathematical and empirical
sciences and becomes more 'critical' (in a roughly Kantian sense), in that
'reflection' is now directed towards identifying and uncovering the necessary
conditions for adequacy and coherence [a]. And Husserl goes even further still in suggesting that the primary function of the
phenomenological method is to investigate what he calls the life-world (Lebenswelt). This is the world we are perceptually
acquainted with and live through. It is
also now seen to be the 'world' from which
the physical sciences originate and on which they are dependent. Indeed if we are to acquire scientific knowledge an understanding
of the Lebenswelt is a prerequisite [b].
PSYCHOLOGY/ PHILOSOPHY OF MAN
[5] In his early Logical Investigations Husserl had rejected the concept of an ego which is its own object,
which, as it were, constitutes itself, or one which is pure or substantial, and
a noumenal 'thing-in-itself'. He
dismisses also the crude empiricist notion of the self as but a set or series
of phenomena ('bundles of perceptions'). However, in the second edition he postulated a 'pure' ego which is not only empirical
(as embodied) but also 'transcendental',
in the sense that its 'essence' is 'instantiated': we apprehend it in the cogito as the
subject of our thinking by means of our application of the phenomenological
reduction in the performance of an intentional act. And it would seem also from the second
edition (and from Ideas I) that this transcendental ego or pure
consciousness whose existence Husserl regarded as indubitable is now seen
as the foundation of the world of experience,
all other things existing relative to it [a].
This latter position has led to the questionable characterization
of Husserl's philosophy as idealist as contrasted with a realist
interpretation according to which there are objects existing independently of
mind and to which we have direct access. He denied he was a subjective idealist in the Berkeleyan sense, but he accepted that his philosophy could be
described as transcendental idealism, though this phrase too is ambiguous. Nevertheless he was already aware of
difficulties with his account which would seem to attribute an independent existence to the transcendental
ego as separable from the empirical self. Indeed, at times he seemed to regard
the transcendental ego as if it were an independent entity which would remain
in existence even if the whole world (and thus including one's empirical self)
were to be destroyed. He therefore came to modify his
thesis and redefined the transcendental ego, arguing that it is correlative to the world rather than
having an absolute existence. This view was already implicit not only in Cartesian Meditations but
also in the earlier unpublished Ideas II, and was eventually fully articulated in his Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Philosophy. Similarly the phenomenal world
itself became the correlate of the "intersubjective community" of individuals
instead of being that which exists in a transcendental phenomenological
reduction of a given individual [b].
Husserl's developing positions in relation to the transcendental ego
and the phenomenal world (to which the
body belongs) are reflected also in his account of freedom. He initially argues that consciousness is causally detached
from the world [Ideas I,
49]. But he later [Ideas II] supposes that the body is in some sense already integrated into the the world's
causality in so far as it is itself a self-motivating mover; or [Crisis, 62] that the ego experiences
itself as a 'living body', that is as a system of organs which it activates Husserl talks of the ego as
acting through the body's 'holding-sway' over its surroundings. Freedom is thereby intrinsic [c].
[6] His final position [in Crisis] would seem to be approximately as follows. An actual, concrete, individual human being is a free, that is, self-motivating unitary
organism but it is considered as having different 'aspects', that is,
conceptually abstractable dependent 'moments' which are instantiations in the
realm of fact of the three regions of essences [a]. Thus, (1) in Nature we have the animate organism studied by natural
science (a) as physical body or material thing (Krper) and (b) as psychological ego; (2) in the Life-World man is
treated as actively engaged in the social-cultural world of human relations,
ethics, the arts, religion, and so on as (a) concrete 'soul' and 'living-body'
(Leib), and (b) the social 'I' or
'mundane ego', characterized by 'spirituality'; (3) as Consciousness there is
the ideal essence the pure or transcendental ego itself, which Husserl
considered to be the subject of experiences, dispositions or 'habitualities',
intentional acts and actions. His transcendental ego is
neither a thinking substance in which thoughts inhere nor the stream of
thoughts themselves. And it is therefore
neither substantial nor separable in the Cartesian manner [b]. He argued further (from 1909) that the transcendental ego as such
is not spatio-temporal (consisting of separate 'past', 'now', and
'future' apprehensions of time as such the view he had held from 1901-7) but is to be conceived of as a
'flow' which is itself the source which constitutes temporality itself [c].
THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
[7] [See especially Logical Investigations II, vi; Ideas I, iv.] In what ways are things known? Husserl made the following distinctions.
(1) Within the realm of Fact we know the material things and
events belonging to the realm of Nature, including ourselves and other people
(as 'moments' of physical body, psyche or soul) by means of sensory intuition
and the constituting consciousness. The
objects, Husserl says, are prescribed by the sense or meaning content of
intentional experience, that is through noemata. The notion of a thing 'in itself' is
therefore superfluous [Ideas I, 47] [a]. Our knowledge of
others as living bodies, their activities and experiences, is gained through an
understanding of their rational and emotional motivations; and this requires
empathy. This is fundamental to the human sciences [b]. He also says that we
can have original intuitions of values in the world which then inform our
motivations [c]. The pure or
transcendental ego, however, as instantiation of the essence Pure Ego, is not
directly intuitable, but qua subject
of consciousness is reached through transcendental reflection [d].
(2) All essences instantiated in the three realms of fact, life-world and
consciousness are known through eidetic intuition and eidetic variation [e].
(3) Meanings or senses (the actual noematic contents of experiences) and
also acts of consciousness are known through the bracketing process and then
phenomenological reduction [f].
It would therefore
seem to follow that knowledge of the empirical self or ego as such and within
the realm of fact (the 'pure I' moments) can be known only as a complex series
of the noemata themselves and thus through phenomenological reflection. Husserl also says that we as egos can be aware of our
experiencing (as contrasted with our awareness of the intentional contents
the noemata of experience): he calls
this 'apperception' [g]. (This is not to be confused with perception which is directed towards
the intentional object as prescribed by the sense or meaning aspect of the
noemata.)
How then does intuition constitute
knowledge? Knowing is itself a mental act which is realized
in the relation between acts of thought and what he terms 'fulfilling
intuitions' [Investigations II,
vi]. The key term 'fulfilment' needs to
be clarified. Suppose I am thinking
about my pen (an intentional act of thinking). If I actually come to perceive the pen, here in front of me on the
table, my thought is said to be fulfilled through this empirical or perceptual
intuition. Knowledge is thus a mental state realized in our
awareness of a relation between the act of thought and its fulfilling empirical
intuition, a recognition of the identity of the object of thought and the
object of perception [h].
Husserl allows degrees of knowing, three kinds of evidence or
"originally giving" [Cartesian
Meditations, 6] [i].
(1) Certainty. In everyday
experience we perceive feel surfaces, see trees, hear birds (though generally
perception is more usually used to refer specifically to vision). In general we do not doubt either that we are
having this experience or that. It is
indeed the tree we are seeing, the bird we are hearing. Such experiences possess the characteristic
of certainty. This is not to say that
mistakes are not possible.
(2) Apodicticity. Apodictic
evidence is stronger than certain evidence and is applicable to what is
absolutely indubitable in a way that our perception of the tree is not. For
his criterion Husserl seems to be thinking here of something like Descartes'
claim to have certain ("clear and distinct") knowledge of himself as a
consciousness of thinking substance though he does not subscribe to Cartesian
metaphysics. (Earlier [see Logical Investigns I,
2nd edn, note to 6], however, he would seem to have regarded the cogito as only adequately self-evident.)
(3) Evidence is said to be 'adequate'. This seems to relate to the notion of fulfilment
introduced in the Investigations [see sec. 7h ]. When we
look at the tree we see particular aspects of it. However, perceptually the experience is open to further
possibilities ('horizons', 'variations'): there is a back to the tree whose colour and
shape we do not see at the moment but could do so if we moved round it. If we were in a position to perceive the
totality of the possibilities, our intendings and meanings would be completely
fulfilled and our knowledge would be said to be adequate. (Clearly this term does not have the usual
sense of sufficiency.) Now if we apply
these grades of evidence to each of the modes of intuition we find that not all
standards are met. Perception, as just
indicated, is not adequate; neither is it apodictic; but it is (usually)
certain. Phenomenological reflection,
however, in general satisfies all three criteria (though Husserl is not always
consistent here, particularly in his analysis of our acts of consciousness in
relation to the life-world).
[8] In Husserl's last writings [The Crisis in European Sciences;
implicit also in Ideas II] it is the 'pre-given'
living-world and our commonsense awareness of the external world of
intersubjectivity that he takes as his starting-point; and it is from this,
through phenomenological reduction, that philosophy is established as a
rigorous science, the natural sciences can be constructed as an abstraction,
and reconciliation between the natural and human sciences achieved [a].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Although Husserl's
philosophy was constantly undergoing change and development, there are a number of key features which are
generally to be found throughout his writings: (1) his use of Brentano's modification of the medieval concepts of
intentionality and 'intended' (as against 'material') objects'; (2) his method
of 'bracketing' and transcendental-phenomenological reduction; and (3) the 'intuition' of essences. (His last
period also saw the introduction of the influential concepts of the
'life-world' and coherence though these too have been shown to have
originated in in much earlier writings.) Nevertheless, his philosophy as a whole is inherently ambiguous; and
much recent scholarship has centred on two interconnected issues: whether he should be regarded as a
commonsense realist or as a transcendental idealist, and whether his
epistemology should be understood in 'foundationalist' terms.
The relationship of his philosophy to
Descartes is central in this dispute. Arguably a merit of Husserl's account of a transcendental ego as neither
a thinking substance in which thoughts inhere nor the stream of thoughts
themselves is that it avoids the problems raised by Descartes' cogito. And some commentators have argued that he goes beyond Descartes with his
concept of intentionality as a nexus of noesis (act) and noema (content) (which
leads to knowledge of the intentional object), his notion of eidetic reduction,
and the intuition of ideal essences. It
follows that he is a transcendental idealist in that (a) the physical world is
constituted by the mind on a foundation of immanence (sensations as the
phenomenal content of intentionally directed mental acts); (b) the constituting
consciousness is the pure transcendental ego; (c) the empirical, psychological
ego is the consciousness which is constituted by the transcendental ego and is
part of the constituted world as a dependent moment of human nature. Thus, although his conception of
consciousness and his foundationalist programme differ in some respects from
Descartes', he remained a Cartesian. And
certainly Husserl himself, at least in his earlier work, accepted the
description of his philosophy as transcendental idealism, though he denied it
was a subjective idealism in the way he supposed Berkeley's to be.
As against this view, some other scholars
have claimed that Husserl's philosophy should not be interpreted in Cartesian
terms at all. It has been suggested that
in the admittedly later Cartesian
Meditations but implicit in earlier writings he is concerned primarily
with the working out of a phenomenology of one's experience of oneself and the
natural world. It is mistaken to suppose
that he raises apodictic certainty to the level of an ideal requirement. Husserl is not engaged in such a quest. He recognises degrees of evidence and
knowledge, and allows that intuitions are revisable revisability being also a
feature of his concept of 'horizon'. On
this interpretation, then, we can say Husserl was not seeking a foundation for
knowledge in the phenomenal content of mental acts still less in an absolute
certainty such as was claimed by Descartes for his cogito (which, as Husserl
correctly pointed out, did not meet Descartes' own apodictic requirements). It can been argued further that Husserl's
notion of foundation was in any case ontological rather than epistemological,
though there is (in Investigations VI) interaction between the two aspects
in that acts of eidetic intuition are founded on lower-level acts involving
sensory content. (They refer to what is
called by some philosophers in the analytic tradition as sense-data or
sensibilia.) Finally, one must have
regard to the later shift towards an emphasis on the 'pre-given' life world and
our commonsense awareness of the external world of intersubjectivity that
Husserl takes as his starting-point. Perhaps then Husserl may be regarded correctly as a foundationalist in
his theory of knowledge but that the nature of the 'foundations' changed from
something approximating to what philosophers working in the earlier 'analytic'
tradition termed sense-data or sensibilia to the something more like
Wittgenstein's 'scaffolding' of ordinary discourse and experience. However, the tension between the two
interpretations remains unresolved.
The precise status of Husserl's
phenomenological statements (that is, the various 'conditions') has also been
frequently questioned. (We may compare
this with the similar problem encountered by the logical positivists'
verification principle.) They are
supposedly non-empirical and yet necessarily true a priori. It has been said
that they cannot be a priori, because
the conditions laid down for phenomena and intentional acts may not be
universal. In a different culture it may
not be possible within the corresponding limits and conditions to distinguish
true from false statements. An
alternative view, however, is that they may be taken to be a priori in so far as they are necessary as preconditions for the
truth and falsity of statements about phenomena. What Husserl says in his Ideas for a Pure Phenomenology would seem to support such an
interpretation (approximately Kantian).
Notwithstanding these
conflicting views perhaps indeed because of them Husserl remains as one of
the most significant thinkers of the twentieth century. As the originator of phenomenology he was a
major influence on a large number of European philosophers including
Heidegger, Scheler, Ortega y Gasset, Jaspers, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Gadamer,
and Ricoeur.
Husserl: Logische Untersuchungen (Logical
Investigations): Part I (Prolegomena to a Pure Logic), 1900; 2nd edn 1913; Part II (Investigations on
Phenomenology and Theory of Knowledge), 1901; 2nd edn (i) 1913, (ii)
1913/22 (trans. J. N.Findlay); Die Idee
der Phnomenologie (1907, published 1950) (The Idea of Phenomenology,
trans. W. P. Alston & G. Nakhnikian); Philosophie
als strenge Wissenschaft (1911) (Philosophy
as Rigorous Science; in Q. Lauer,
ed., Phenomenology and the Crisis
of Philosophy); Ideen zu einer reinen
Phnomenologie und phnomenologischen
Philosophie (1913) (Ideas pertaining
to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy: Book I trans. F. Kersten; Book II trans. R. Rojcewicz & A, Schuwer;
Book III trans. T. E. Klein & W. E. Pohl); Cartesianische Meditationen (1929) (published 1950) (Cartesian Meditations: Introduction to
Phenomenology, trans. D. Cairns); Die Krisis der Europischen Wissenschaften
und die transzendentale Philosophie (1936) (The Crisis of European Philosophy
and Transcendental Philosophy: An
Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy, trans. D. Carr). See
also Husserl's article "Phenomenology" in the 1929 Encyclopedia Britannica. Selections from his writings with commentary are to be found in R.
Solomon (ed.), Phenomenology and
Existentialism.
Studies
D. Bell, Husserl.
J. M.
Edie, Edmund Husserl's
Phenomenology: A Critical Commentary.
M.
Natanson, Edmund Husserl: Philosopher of Infinite Tasks.
P.
Ricoeur, Husserl: An Analysis of his Philosophy.
M. Russell, Husserl: A
Guide for the Perplexed.
Collection of essays
B. Smith
and D. Woodruff Smith (eds), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl.
CONNECTIONS
Husserl
[1a] |
[Later] rejection of psychologism in
mathematics and logic; necessary, a priori field of knowledge; psychology is only
probable based on inductive
arguments |
Kant→
Mill→
Brentano→
→Frege→
Russell
→Merleau-Ponty |
[1b]
[1a]
[1a 1d]
[1a]
[1f]
[1a] |
[1b; also 3b] |
Formal maths
part of formal logic; both part of pure logic systematic structure of laws/ theories; 'ideal' categories of meaning |
Plato→
Frege→ |
[1d]
[1b c 2b] |
[1d; cf. 3c] |
Distinction
between 'referent' and 'sense' ('content' real as instantiation of the ideal species); sense does not determine reference |
Plato→
Aristotle→
Frege→ |
[1c]
[4b]
[2e] |
[2b] |
Rejection of materialism, reductionism, positivism, naturalism, relativism, historicism, irrationalism, idealism |
[representative: ]
Hegel→
Mill→
Dilthey→
→Ortega y Gasset |
[1a c 9a]
[1k]
[1b]
[1a] |
[3a c e] |
Three
realms Essence, Fact, and Meaning:
i Essence (ideal): contains formal and material essences |
Plato→
Peirce
Frege |
[1c]
[2a]
[2i] |
[3b; also 1b] |
Formal ontology
(concerned with formal essences) + formal logic + meaning categories makes up Logic (unifying science of necessary interconnected truths) |
Plato→
Frege→ |
[1d 3a]
[2b] |
[3c; cf. 1d] |
ii
Fact: concrete, spatio-temporal, in which essences are instantiated (individuals, states of affairs, events/ experiences |
Plato→
Aristotle→ |
[2c]
[4b] |
[3e; see 7f; also 1d] |
iii Meaning: contents (real noesis,
and intentional noema)
of intentional experiences/ acts |
Searle |
[1c] |
[4a; cf. 2c d] |
(Later)
phenomenological method 'critical' describes criteria, necessary conditions for adequacy and coherence of experience |
Kant→ |
[1c] |
[5c] |
Freedom; the living body as self-motivating mover; reconciliation of freedom and causality? |
Descartes
Kant→
Scheler |
[3h]
[7a 10d]
[4b] |
[6c] |
Transcendental ego not spatio-temporal but 'flow' which itself is source of and constitutes temporality |
Kant→
→Scheler
→Heidegger
→Sartre |
[3b]
[3c]
[3d]
[3a] |
[7a] |
Knowledge of things, events, people (qua 'objects') from sensory intuition; no 'thing-in-itself' apart from constituting consciousness |
Descartes→
Hume→
Kant→
Hegel
Brentano→
→Scheler |
[2b]
[1c]
[2d]
[1a]
[2c]
[1c] |
[7c] |
Intuitions of values; inform motivations |
→Scheler |
[2b] |
[7g] |
Apperception awareness of our experiencing |
Leibniz
Kant |
[2d]
[3b] |
[7h] |
Knowledge as mental state/ act realized in awareness of relation between act and its empirical 'fulfilling' intuition; identity of objects of thought and
perception |
Aristotle
Searle |
[16e]
[2c] |
[7i] |
Degrees of knowing and evidence: certainty, apodicticity, adequacy; 'non- foundational' account |
Descartes→
Brentano |
[1b 2a]
[2c] |
[8a; cf. 2a] |
The
Life-world pre-given: commonsense awareness of intersubjectivity starting point (via phenomenological reduction) for 'rigorous' philosophy, and reconciliation of natural and human sciences |
Dilthey→
→Scheler
→Heidegger
→Gadamer
→Merleau-Ponty
→Ricoeur |
[1b 2a b]
[4e]
[2a 3c]
[1b d 3a]
[1a 1c 2a 3c]
[4c] |