DUNS SCOTUS
'SCOTISM'
Born at Maxton,
Roxburghshire (Scotland), John Duns Scotus was ordained in the Franciscan Order
in 1291 and then studied at Oxford and Paris (1293-96). After lecturing at Oxford he returned to
Paris in 1302 only to be banished a year later for favouring the Pope against
the King. But he was soon back and
received his doctorate in theology in 1305. He later taught at Cologne, where he died. He was given the title 'Doctor Subtilis' (Subtle Doctor) because of his dialectical skill.
METAPHYSICS/ RELIGIOUS
PHILOSOPHY
[1] For Scotus metaphysics and theology are distinct
and have their own particular concerns the former with being (ens) and its attributes, the latter with
God [see, for
example, Free Questions, 3 and 7, and Opus oxon. I and II]. He thinks of being as an essentially indefinable concept of that in
whose existence there is no contradiction; and this applies to being in all its
modes including God, individual created things, and concepts. Metaphysics, however, cannot attain to an
understanding of the true nature of being as such, as reason is limited and deals with the natural order and sense experience. Theology on the other hand is not understood as a
'science'; it is grounded in revelation which is the concern of faith,
and the 'knowledge' it provides us with can only be 'practical' [ibid.,
Prologue 4, 31]. It follows that while we can apprehend God through this central notion of
being, beyond this we can know nothing
about Him [a].
For Scotus all features of the world that pass beyond the physical
(and which are not included in Aristotle's categories) are transcendentals. He
distinguishes between finite
beings (creatures) and infinite being (God); being is common to both. He distinguishes further between 'convertible' attributes (passiones convertibiles) and
'disjunctive' attributes (passiones
disiunctae) [see, for example, ibid. I, 3, qq.ii and iii, and 8, q.iii]. The
first includes notions such as true, good, one, which are interchangeable with being in that there is
no real distinction between them, only a formal one [see sec. 2]. The 'pure' perfections of God, such as omnipotence, wisdom, and
free-will, in whose definitions there are no limitations when applied to
him, are also convertible attributes. The second, however, covers such concepts as necessity and contingency, and potentiality and
actuality, which are not interchangeable with being if they are
considered separately. Thus some beings
are necessary and some contingent. All
beings must of course be one or the other. Scotus says we can
move from finite disjunctive attributes to infinite being, but not the other
way round; a necessary existence does not entail a contingent one [b]. The deduction from potentiality to actuality or from contingency to
actuality, according to Scotus, presupposes that 'being' is a univocal concept (he rejects the analogical account). By this he means that the concept, although
applicable to different types of being, always has the same sense referring
to a universal nature. Thus it would be
contradictory to say that God is being but that His creatures are not. God is of course being in a different way,
but He and His creatures must have something sufficiently in common to allow a valid deduction from the existence of an attribute possessed by finite
being to its predication of the infinite being God in a perfect sense. Univocity is thus clearly essential to
underpin Scotus's metaphysics [ibid.]. The univocal concept of being as such,
abstracted from individual beings (it is the ultimate abstraction), is a
logical concept. Considered as signifying other signs and not
things (called intentio secunda in
medieval logic), it has only a formal mental existence as ens rationis). And although grounded in reality, having objective reference (when it is considered
as intentio prima, as signifying
things), there is no actual extramentally existent thing which, while
corresponding to the universal concept, is separate from it [see, for
example, ibid. II, 3, q.i] [c]. Scotus therefore (arguably) tends to the view that our 'subjective' mental and
linguistic structures, while referring to the 'objective' realm, condition the
way we experience the being of nature (ens
naturae) [d]. Perhaps we can say then
that beings are 'subjectively objective'. Underlying this position is the important idea of intentionality ('intentional inexistence'): all
things are to be understood as the referred objects of mental acts of understanding [e].
[2] Another important idea in his metaphysics is that
of an 'objective formal distinction'
which is more objective than a virtual or mental distinction but is yet in some sense less than the real
distinction [a]. He calls this distinctio formalis a parte rei ('formal distinction on the side
of/ in respect of the thing') [ibid. I, 35 and 36; also IV, 13]. Thus, while he regards essence and
existence as distinguishable, they are nevertheless inseparable, in that
'existence' applies strictly to essences of individual things, which have been actualized from the Ideas in
God (and which exist qua known) [b]. In the same way he distinguishes between the
physical nature of an object and its 'thisness'.
(haecceitas) [II, 3]. What he means by these terms can be explained
as follows. [See ibid. II, 3; Metaphysics V, 1 and 2.] An individual or 'composite' thing is made up of matter and its determining form or essence (its haecceitas) [c], as well as other forms he thus accepted the plurality
of forms, matter too having its own form
of corporeity [d] albeit
imperfect by comparison with the soul, as well as the capacity of matter to
receive other forms when substantial change occurs [see, for example, Comms IV, 11, iii]. And while he accepted the doctrine of hylomorphism, it is doubtful
that he should be understood as intending to extend this beyond corporeal
beings [Opus oxon. II, 12,
q.i] [e]. Matter, however, is not a mere potentiality; if God so willed, it could
exist on its own, separate from forms [ibid. II, 12, qq.i and ii] [f]. Indeed matter must exist to receive forms,
and it must underlie substantial change. Scotus says that although not a form it is 'in act'. But he argues that matter is not the principle of individuation. If it were, then in a change of substance
that which is produced and that from which it originates would be identical,
despite a difference in form [ibid. II, 3, qq.v and vi]. What makes, say, Socrates that individual thing is his 'thisness',
whereas his 'humanity' is attributed to his nature. Yet his haecceitas and his nature are not really
separable, though they are distinguishable in so far as we can abstract the
nature as a universal. But Scotus
denies that the nature of, for example, 'humanity', common to Socrates and
other human beings, is numerically identical in them all. Universals actually exist in the
intellect, but are common only in the sense that they refer to 'natures' which
are, however, unique to each individual. The distinction between an
individual's nature and its 'thisness' is an 'objective formal' one [g]. He also
rejected the theory of 'seminal reasons' [h] on
the grounds that change can be accounted for by the causal activity of created
efficient agents themselves [Reports II,
18, 1].
[3] As for his treatment of God, while
He is strictly the proper object of theology, Scotus allows that His existence can be proved [see especially Op. ox., II, 2]; and he offers a number of
arguments. He accepts the ontological argument, although he
first 'colours' it to show there is no contradiction in the idea that God is
the most perfect being and is thus possible [see, for example, Comms Prologue 4; Reports, Prologue]. In
general he appeals to a posteriori proofs from God's effects in the world. But although the 'natural philosopher' can
argue for a first mover to account for the fact of motion, for proof of the existence of God as first
and efficient cause the
arguments must be metaphysical. His main argument is based on the facts of contingency, finitude, and relative perfection in the
world. While we can admit an infinite
regress of successive contingent causes (he calls this an 'accidental' chain), for example of parent to child, the total chain itself must be
assimilated to a set of 'essential'
causes which includes all relevant
causal factors and rests ultimately in the most 'eminent' or perfect being, the
first efficient (and thereby exemplary), intelligent cause. This first cause must be necessary (it cannot not exist) [a] and renders accidental chains necessary and therefore
transcendent; for if it were not, it would itself belong to the chain and
thereby be contingent.
There can
be only one ultimate or first cause. If there were two beings possessing a common nature of necessary being,
their separate individualities would not be necessary being. A first cause must also be essentially simple, lacking matter, form and
accidental qualities, and must be absolutely infinite Being or divine essence
in which are grounded all perfections (goodness, truth, justice, and so on) to
an infinite degree. And God must be infinite if
He is to know and produce an infinity of objects. Furthermore, only an infinite being can
satisfy our finite will's desire for an infinite object. As there is no incompatibility between being
and infinity, the most superior being must be infinite. It follows from Scotus's arguments that all God's attributes are really
identical with themselves and the divine essence, though they are formally
distinct. Nevertheless, he
maintains that while God's
infinity, necessity, uniqueness, freedom, and creative power are demonstrable
philosophically, other attributes (such as omnipotence, justice, goodness,
providence) are a matter of revelation and faith and cannot be confirmed by
reason [b].
Scotus distinguishes between the divine essence, intellect, and
will. His essence is
logically, but not temporarily prior to his intellect,
that is, the divine Idea, and is thus not identical with it. It contains
implicitly the intelligible 'natures' as actual or possible 'imitations' of the
essence the exemplars of the things He wills to create. The exemplars thus depend on His knowledge of His
essence [c]; and He knows His created things
through their possibility in his essence and not through the exemplary Ideas
themselves. And they are infinite in
number but God chooses to create only some of the possible corresponding
sensible objects. [See ibid. I, 35-36.] His intellect is thus subordinate to his will [IV, 49,q.ii]. His creativity is necessary in that His love
for himself is part of His essential nature and has to be manifested. At the same time His willing, if it is to be perfect, must be free [d]. God thus 'assents' to the necessity of His love. But while Scotus accepts that God, as first efficient cause,
can create immediately out of nothing (otherwise there would be no
mediate creation, that is, the existing world), he does not believe creation in time can be proved [e]. Further, in so far as God
is creator by will and not by essence (in which case creation would be
necessary), His relation to creatures is 'mental' and not 'real'. The relation of creatures to God, however, is
real, though it is only through His will that contingent creatures can 'meet'
Him as necessary being [Ibid. I, 3 and 17; 35 and 36; Repub.
I, 45]. As for the problem of evil, God providentially allows for
its existence in the world to a limited degree in so far as He wishes men to
learn from error much of the evil resulting from their misuse of freedom [f].
PSYCHOLOGY
[4] [Op. ox., IV, 43, q.ii] The rational soul
is the substantial form of man, says Scotus; it is what makes us alive and
human. It is not itself a substance (a
composite of body and soul) [a]. He argues as follows. Each of our
senses has its own proper object colour, sound, and so on. The intellect, however, 'cognises' being. It does not depend on a sense organ and can
pass beyond the senses to apprehend, for example, relations. We also know
ourselves to be free beings. Now,
neither intellectual understanding nor voluntary acts can be brought about by a
material form. Our intellect and will
therefore transcend the organic and must be functions of spiritual form. This is the rational soul. Its 'activity' and 'passivity' are not
regarded by Scotus as distinct powers [On the Soul 13 though
this may not be a wholly genuine work of Scotus's (see Wolter)]. As for the 'faculties' intellectual, sensitive, and vegetative
these are distinct only in the 'objective formal' sense. The soul thus brings about the perfection of
the whole man [b]. At death, although the composite being undergoes corruption, both the
soul in its higher form and the body survive (the latter by virtue of its
imperfect corporeal form), albeit temporarily [see Op. ox., IV,
43, q.ii passim.]. However, for Scotus neither the immortality of the soul nor the
resurrection of the body can be demonstrated with certainty; they are only
probable, and are to be accepted on faith [c]. A priori arguments, based on the nature of the rational soul in
its intellectual aspect considered as a form transcending the composite
being, do not show, moreover, that such a form is either necessarily
independent of the composite or self-subsistent. As for a posteriori moral arguments,
for example, ones grounded in man's desire for beatitude or in his need for
sanctions after death, these are, for Scotus, even less satisfactory. Likewise, a natural desire to avoid death
(found also in non-human animals) does not prove immortality. We would first have to show that immortality
is possible before arguing to it from the recognition of any conscious
desire. Finally, we cannot appeal to the
hope of rewards in the next life for good behaviour in this one, because we do
not know that God will reward us.
As in the case of God, Scotus stresses the primacy of the human will over intellect [see Op. ox. IV, 49, qq.ii and iii; I,
8]. The intellect must therefore necessarily assent to any truths it
may apprehend. Likewise, the will, in so far as it is a
natural inclination to self-perfection, necessarily desires happiness. But the intrinsic nature of the will lies in its freedom [ibid. I, 17, q.iii] [d]: it can choose to act or not to act to realize
some end. And although knowledge is
needed to apprehend such an end, the will can, through its freedom, direct the
intellect to attend to a particular object.
KNOWLEDGE
[5] It is in the very
nature of the soul to know. So what does
Scotus understand by 'knowledge', and how does the soul attain it? [See especially ibid. I, 2, q.vii; 3, qq.iv, ix; 9, q.ii.]. Knowledge in the primary sense consists in the intellect's apprehension
of being as being. But Scotus
says that in this life being can be known only as it is manifested in material
things. The starting-point for this 'secondary' knowledge is
sense experience; and there are no innate ideas [Metaphys. 1, ii] [a]. Scotus also rejects any involvement of 'illumination' divine
or intellectual [Op. Ox. I, 3, iv] [b]. He distinguishes between intuitive and abstractive secondary knowledge [for
example, ibid. I, 3, iii; 2, vii] [c]. The former is 'perfect' when knowledge is
immediate of a present object but 'imperfect' when of an existent or real
object considered in the memory or as existing in the future. Abstractive knowledge, on the other hand, is
of the essence of a thing without regard to whether it actually exists or
not. Knowledge is firstly of individuals, singular things
(their 'thisness'), of essences or forms, and of first principles implicit in
complexes (for example that the whole is greater than the part) the intellect being moved by
sensations or imagination (comprising phantasms) [cf. On the Soul, 22, 3]. Knowledge is effected when, through the cooperation of its
active and passive functions, the intellect interacts with the 'intelligible
likenesses' of objects (sensory or intelligible species), which convey to it
'their common natures'. The intellect
can also transcend the sense to achieve knowledge of universals and relations [d]. However, our intuition
of singular things is confused. Scotus
attributes this to a human limitation resulting from original sin, or it
may reflect the need for a harmonization of our powers [Op. ox. II, 3, vi and ix; Free
Questions 13, viii-x]. This
limitation also accounts for our
inability to have any immediate intuition of the soul. (As for God, there can be no knowledge of the divine essence in this
life or after it [e]. ) Scotus says
there is a role for inductive
procedures. Thus we can come to a knowledge of natural
causes of effects by generalizing from our experience of number of
instances. But for the most part he uses demonstrative (deductive)
proofs and tries to show that an effect follows logically or
'self-evidently' from its cause; such knowledge is more certain [f].
ETHICS
[6] [See especially Opus oxon., II, 5, 7, 18, 40 and 41; III, 19, 37; IV, 1, 5, 14 and
15.] 'Goodness' for Scotus is to be
understood in several ways. A thing is transcendentally good in so far as it is a being, that is a
positive entity, which can be desired. This is a property of all beings. A thing is naturally (or secondarily) good when it possesses harmoniously all those qualities which are
'proper' to that thing or 'becoming' to it, just as something is made
beautiful by virtue of its colour, shape, and so on. Such goodness is an 'accident' of being [a]. Likewise an action or activity is naturally good when it is in harmony
with its efficient cause, its end, and its form. To be morally good, however, an action must be freely willed, and the 'circumstances' of the
act must all be present. These
include objectivity (through the conformity of the willed action to what is morally right [Op.
ox., II, 40, qq.ii, iii] this is primary moral goodness, and is intuitable by the reason without
divine illumination); and also the requirement that it be done for the right end and with the right intention [b]. If the act is performed by the will having regard to all these
circumstances, especially the intention, then it is said to possess secondary moral goodness [II, 7, q.i]. The absence
or even deficiency of any one of these circumstances will affect the goodness
of the action. Thus a good end sought by
a bad means will make the action evil; while doing something positive (for
example, giving alms) as a result of mere inclination or impulse rather than
with an explicitly good intention (that is, not referred to the infinite good
actually or virtually) will render the act morally 'indifferent', that is, neither good nor bad [ibid.]. Loving God is an
exception; it can never be morally evil, requiring only conformity to right
reason. What, then, makes reason as the
objective standard 'right'? Scotus seems
to hold the view that an
objectively moral natural law is intrinsic to God's creation and cannot be
altered. However, he distinguishes between the objective content of the moral law and
the obligation on us as finite
beings to perform right actions [Op. ox. IV, 14]. This obligation originates from God; and sin
is disobedience to God's will. God himself can of course will
only what is objectively good which He perceives by His intellect. But Scotus also says that God can give us dispensation
from some secondary laws which are in accordance with primary self-evident
moral principles (but not from the
primary laws themselves or from those deducible from them [see, for example, Op. ox., III, 37] [c].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Scotus's philosophy is sui generis. Critical of both Augustinianism (with respect to the role of divine illumination)
and Thomas's use of Aristotelian
terminology to describe God, Scotus marks the beginning of a radical change in
medieval thought. In effect he set out
to reinterpret the relationship of faith to reason: reason is now limited to a metaphysics of
Being, while faith is concerned with divine revelation. Thus we find a greater place being accorded
to reason and in consequence a delimiting of the sphere of natural
theology. It is only through Being as
a univocal abstraction common to all existents, finite and infinite that a
link with God is retained and His existence provable. Scotus also stresses God's complete freedom
(His intellect being subordinated to His will, as is the case also with human
creatures) and His necessary existence (created individuals being
contingent). Scotus's originality is
shown particularly in his concept of 'thisness' (the immediate manifestation of essence or form) as the
individuating principle; and in his use of the Franciscan doctrine of
'objective formal distinction' a distinction which delineates neither the
subjective (mental) nor the objective (real), and which is applied to essences
in things and the human soul. His
account of individuation and his emphasis on immediate knowledge of the
individual thing its 'thisness' by the intellect working with the senses
are of particular interest for the role they played in informing the concept of
'inscape' introduced by the 19th century Jesuit poet Gerard Manley
Hopkins to refer to the essential individuality and oneness of natural things.
From the standpoint of earlier
philosophers in either of the two main traditions Scotus's weakening of the
link between reason and faith was a dangerous move. Not only (it was argued) does God become
virtually unknowable, and the continuity between God and his creation broken,
but reason is now set free to undermine faith and authority although this was not the intention of Scotus
himself. On the other hand, from the
point of view of thinkers who had no religious axe to grind, the confining of
philosophy to the sensible natural order was to be regarded as a positive and
liberating feature of Scotist thought.
CONNECTIONS
Duns Scotus