SUAREZ
'SUAREZANISM'
(MODIFIED THOMISM)
Francisco Suarez was
born at Granada, Spain, the son of a lawyer. He was admitted to the Jesuit Order in 1564 and studied philosophy. He
later studied canon law at the University of Salamanca. From 1571 until his retirement in 1616 he
taught philosophy and theology at a number of Jesuit colleges and universities,
finally becoming a professor at CoImbra (1597-1616). He was a prolific writer and was the central figure in the
sixteenth century revival of scholasticism in Spain. He was known as Doctor Eximius ('distinguished teacher').
METAPHYSICS / PSYCHOLOGY
[1] [Metaphysical Disputations 1 and 2.] Metaphysics is the science that studies being qua being. By 'being' Suarez means that which does or can exist; being is 'real essence' that
which does not involve a contradiction and which is not constructed by the
mind. And being is divided into necessary being (being in itself ens a se) and contingent being (ens ab alio) [a]
which is dependent on or participating in being in itself, that is, God. Existent things include 'transcendental attributes' [ibid. 3-11] [b]:
unity, truth, goodness [3], material and immaterial things, and substances and
accidents. The metaphysician is concerned primarily with immaterial things but arrives at general categories of being through a
consideration of material things. He
also deals with the concept of being, but again not as an abstraction but as it
is realized in existent things. This
concept refers to what all actually existent beings have in common, that is,
their likeness to each other. And he
says that all creatures are in being by virtue of their relation to God in so
far as they participate in or imitate His being. But being is not a universal concept. Suarez held that the relationship between finite beings in general
and God's infinite being is not univocal but one of analogical attribution [De
Legibus 2 & 28] [c]. He distinguishes further between being as real essence and being
as the act of existing, but he places more emphasis on the
former. In God they are one and the same [30] [d]. God possesses all perfections. He is the one being,
uncreated, infinite, all-wise, pure act, without 'composition'. However, according to Suarez, there are different ways of
possessing perfections. Perfections (for
example, wisdom) exist formally and can be predicated formally of God if
they do not of themselves contain any imperfection or limitation. But considered as the source of (limited) wisdom in finite things God possesses this perfection 'eminently' [e]; and it is then predicable of Him
formally only by analogy. Suarez accepts the Aristotelian/ Thomist account of the four causes (material, efficient,
formal, and final) [13-27] [f] and also the causal argument for God's existence [29]. While
everything that is made or produced (as against being moved) is so by another,
either there can be no infinite regress or an external cause would be required
to ground the infinite series. Such a
'cause' or unproduced product is God though Suarez argues that to show that
this is God one must first establish
that there is only one
uncreated necessarily self-existing being. And this must be so, for if many beings have
the same nature what makes them individuals would have to lie outside their
essence; whereas in the
case of the unique God his individuality
belongs to His very existence [g].
[2] As for finite beings [30 and
31], Suarez allows that there is in them a distinction between
'existing' essence and 'actual' essence, but this is only a logical or mental
distinction, not a real one [a], although it is
objectively grounded in that
creatures do not exist necessarily. It is "a distinction of the reason as fundamental in
the thing" (distinctio rationis cum
fundamento in re) [31]. Existence is in fact just the actual essence
itself; it is not received in and therefore not limited by a potentiality. Actual existent essences created by God are
thus contingent in their very nature. Because this distinction is not real the metaphysical union of existence and essence of all
created beings to form an ens per
se unum can be called
a 'composite' only in an analogical sense [31]; whereas it is a genuine (and physical) composition such as the union of
matter and form, for example, which constitutes bodies or individual (primary) substance [b], that is,
immediately existing things comprising species and differentia, not dependent
attributes. Rejecting Aquinas's
postulation of matter and Ockham's haecceitas as the principle of individuation, Suarez regards both form
and matter as individuating factors [c], form being the
primary one as sufficient to determine the numerical uniqueness of the
individual thing, while matter is
relevant to the distinction between
individuals in respect of, say, quantity [5]. However, he also allows that individuality itself adds to the common
essence of a thing something real which is mentally distinct from the essence
and which with it constitutes the individual metaphysically. Primary substances as actual essences are
existents. But he also says a primary substance is a suppositum, that is, it has subsistence,
is not supported by anything else [34]. This subsistence is a special mode of existing, namely as a
substance, added to the actual essence. Accidents subsist in a different mode as dependent attributes. Form and
matter have their own special modes as
well as a mode in union [d]. Secondary substances are universals [ibid. 6], but while these are grounded in real things, they
themselves have no real existence. However, he rejects
the idea that they are either merely mental contructions or words [e].
[3] The soul too may be said to have different modes
of subsistence [a] according as to
whether it is joined to the body or separated after death. To account for knowledge, Suarez distinguishes an active intellect and
a passive intellect. The active intellect can know individual material objects directly. The passive intellect, assisted by the active
intellect, conforms to the representations or 'likenesses' of the 'phantasms'
it receives through sense-experience [b] and thence
attains to knowledge of
universals by abstraction [6]. Despite
Suarez's abstractionism and his view that all individual beings are individual
essences, he rejects both conceptualist and nominalist theories [c].
[4] Relations [47, 54. Suarez
distinguishes between real
and mental relations. Mental relations, which
include logical relations such as subject-predicate and genus and species, as
well as negations, privations, and purely mental relations, are entia rationis, which have being objectively in the mind. They are called entia by way of analogy with being. As for real
relations, only those which cannot be separated from the essences of their
subjects belong to the category of relations proper. For example, it is an intrinsic
characteristic of the essence of an existent creature that it belongs to the Creator. Matter and form are similarly related. These are called 'transcendental relations' [a]. Relations such as that which obtains
between, for example, two white things no
longer exist when one of the things
ceases to exist. Such relations,
although real, do not therefore belong to the category of relations.
[5] Man's participatory dependence on God
[31] raises a problem in relation to choice. Suarez. was concerned
to avoid the difficulty that God's omniscience might seem
incompatible with human freedom, human actions being predetermined. He therefore utilized the theory of congruism [a]. God has
'intermediate knowledge' (scientia media) of what an individual will do if he is
given grace to enable him to act freely. But Suarez introduces a distinction
between 'congruous' grace, appropriate to the circumstances of actions and
which will therefore gain the consent of the individual will, and 'incongruous' grace, which, although sufficient to
enable the will to act, is yet
unsuitable and does not get the individual's consent. God, however, knows what graces would be
congruous.
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY/ PHILOSOPHY OF LAW
[6] [See On Laws.] Suarez distinguished four kinds or levels of law. Eternal law is God's freely
willed decree and is revealed to man in divine law, which he is obliged
to obey. Natural law comprises general,
primary, and immutable moral principles, such as to do good, or to worship God,
and secondary moral principles
derived from them. Man perceives natural
law through the natural light of reason, but it originates from God's
will: He has through his reason ordained that certain kinds of
acts should be prescribed in so far as they are intrinsically good, that
is, harmonize with rational natures and lead to the common good. He is not, however, the direct volitional cause of good and evil
actions. Human law [a], on which political philosophy is based, has
to be grounded in divine law or natural law. The state for
Suarez is 'natural', not an artificial social contract. But it is the community which gives power to
the legislature, and although this is underpinned by God the people
remain free to choose their actual form of government. While approving of monarchy, Suarez says the people have the
right to depose their ruler even a legitimate one if he is unjust [b].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Suarez's philosophy may be characterized as
a development and modification of the central tenets of Thomism, and the
criticisms which might be made of his system are similar to those which apply
to that of Aquinas. But he is important
for his revival of scholasticism in the early Renaissance period, and
especially for his legal and political philosophy. Noteworthy is his rejection
of the view that theology can be
sundered from metaphysics; indeed he argues that theology requires a systematic metaphysics if it is to be articulated. But perhaps the most controversial issue,
concerns his views about the relationship between essence and existence. Most of the later philosophers who may be supposed
to have been influenced by him, such as Vico, Descartes, and Leibniz, have
interpreted him as an 'essentialist' (and indeed Aquinas came to be similarly
interpreted by association, as it were). However, some scholars (for example, Copleston) have argued that this
view of Suarez is misleading if not false; and moreover that the differences
between Aquinas and Suarez are less marked than has been supposed. If existence and essence are identified
respectively with actuality (being) and potentiality (non-being), then clearly
Aquinas was correct in making a real distinction between them in finite things (although they remain inseparable).
But Suarez says that actual existence and actual essence are only mental
distinctions, albeit objectively founded in creation and contingency. Existence is limited by essence not because
it is a potentiality (Aquinas's view) but because existence is nothing but enacted essence; it is
limited by its being what it is a finite, contingent being dependent on and
participating in God. Copleston also
points to this dependency (reinforced by Suarez's emphasis on production rather
than motion) as characterizing an existential aspect in his thought.
CONNECTIONS
Suarez