PEIRCE
(1839 1914)
PRAGMATISM
Charles Sanders
Peirce was brought up in an academic atmosphere in Cambridge (Massachusetts),
where his father was a professor of mathematics and astronomy at Harvard. He himself studied science at the university,
gaining a degree in chemistry in 1863. He subsequently worked as an astronomer in the Observatory and as a
physicist for the United States Coast and Geodetic Survey (1861-91), devoting
his spare time to study and research in philosophy. He also lectured briefly at Harvard on the
history of science and then logic, and taught logic at John Hopkins University
(1879-84). But he held no other
university posts. He settled in
Pennsylvania in 1887 and devoted the rest of his life to writing.
[Sources: References are to individual books and
articles, or to the volumes and paragraphs in the Collected Papers of
Charles Sanders Peirce, vols I-VI (ed. Hartshorne and Weiss), and vols
VII-VIII (ed. Burks).]
LOGIC/ METHODOLOGY
[1] While Peirce agreed that logic is a formal enquiry he also stressed that it
has a psychological aspect and is concerned with inferences, which he came to
regard as fundamental, in so far as they govern the role played by
propositions. (This eventually led him to reject synthetic a
priori propositions.) More
generally he thought of logic as a 'semiotic', that is,
a theory of signs. But he was
critical of conceptualist and 'inner privacy' approaches. He regarded all propositions as exemplifying a
single sign relation grounded in the copula. He also tended to see terms as rudimentary propositions [a] in that noun terms connote
characteristics. He
accepted the traditional distinction between deductive and inductive inference,
but also introduced a third type, namely, 'abduction'. By this he understood a process which
involves inference from what he called a 'surprising fact' to an explanation
which 'if true' would render the fact no longer surprising. Abduction thus has a methodological function to give rise to
explanatory hypotheses. 'Induction'
refers to the statistical testing of hypotheses to determine the probability of
their truth [b].
Having identified difficulties in Kant's
logic, he divided 'logical sciences' into three kinds, each
dealing with a different mode of reference of signs in subject-predicate logic of
propositions:
(1) Speculative grammar. This
studies the relationships
of signs as 'abstractions'. The mind as
interpreter (we might think of it in terms of a 'unifier') relates a
predicate, as sign ('representamen'), to
the subject by virtue of the predicate's reference to abstract attributes (as
'ground'); and this gives rise in the interpreter to a more developed sign (the
'interpretant'). This division of logic is concerned with formal conditions of meaningfulness.
(2) Critical logic, is concerned with the formal conditions of the truth of
symbols and the relationship of signs to their objects. It deals with various kinds of argument.
(3) Speculative rhetoric. This sets
out the formal conditions of the 'force' of symbols. It examines the reference of signs to other
signs in human or other minds. It is
these latter signs that are called the interpretants) [c]. The total intended interpretant of a symbol (as a term,
or in a proposition or an argument) is the meaning,
exhibited in conditional propositions and ultimately verifiable empirically. This in turn presupposes the existence
of a 'reality' or general 'essence' as a
possibility which can be actualized; and Peirce accordingly rejects nominalist
theories of meaning. Nevertheless he also seems to suggest that any such 'transcendent' is
ultimately inacessible in that reference is indefinite [d]:
Anything which
determines something else (its interpretant) to refer to which itself refers
(its object) in the same way, this interpretant becoming in turn a sign, and
so on ad infinitum. [Elements
of Logic]
Symbols come into
being by development from other signs. It is "only out of symbols that a new symbol can grow" [Omne symbolum de symbolo]. "If the series of successive interpretants
comes to an end, the sign is thereby rendered imperfect." [Elements].
Logic is fundamental to Peirce's general philosophy, that is,
his theory of knowledge and metaphysics, in so far as he supposed that fundamental categories and principles can be
derived from it. (And indeed in
his final period [from the 1890s until his death] he presented his pragmatism
and his metaphysics in terms of abductive inference and heuristic hypotheses
[see 'Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction', Harvard lecture VII].) These
fundamental categories originated in the Kantian triad of ontological categories, cosmology
(matter), psychology (mind), and theology (God). And in the light of his new classification of
logic he sought to show that they are derived by a process of abstraction from
the three referential aspects of signs, and thereby grounded in the basic logical relation of 'signhood' [see 'On a New List of Categories'] [e].
.The
discovery of the logic of relations,
to the development of which he himself made a major contribution, led Peirce to
reject the subject-predicate form in favour of the 'illative relation' (that
is, a relation expressed by the conditional 'if... then...' or
'therefore', and which he supposed to be the fundamental notion of logic), and
thus to revise his account of the meaning of a term. He also rejected any reduction of
propositional relations to class relations. 'Illative relations' (which
later logicians called 'material implications') comprehended formal relations;
and he regarded logic in general as 'psychological', having to consider
inferences, rather than just formal
relationships characterized by implication. A proposition, he said, is a 'rudimentary' inference. Logic for Peirce therefore was a kind of 'logic of inquiry'. This gave rise to his central theory of
pragmatism [see 'The Fixation of Belief', 'How to Make Our Ideas Clear']. He regarded pragmatism he was later (1905)
(in response to James's transformation of pragmatism into a theory of truth) to
call it pragmaticism as a method
of reflection ('methodeutic') for "rendering ideas clear" [5.13,
note]. It is essentially a theory of meaning. He defined this thus:
In order to ascertain the meaning of an intellectual
conception one should consider what practical consequences might conceivably
result by necessity from the truth of that conception; and the sum of these
consequences will constitute the entire meaning of the conception [Collected Papers, 5.9].
What
the conception (of an object) means is a set of 'habits' involving the object, or laws describing behaviour. Peirce thought of these laws as conditional
propositions which link the testing of them to the sum of practical consequences analysable in phenomenal terms. Thus I can say I know what, for example,
'wet' means if I can relate it to how a certain liquid feels, what it does when
I put my hand into it, and so on. Peirce's position is thus initially basically 'realist' in the sense that for a concept to be
meaningful requires that the conditional propositions should be verifiable,
and that therefore the
meaning relates to something actual a real and permanent possibility. 'Hypotheses' are themselves meaningful if the
practical consequences can be conceived as possible [f]. However, further
developments in logic concerning counterfactual conditionals tended to
undermine his commitment to realism; it became difficult to distinguish
pragmatically between real and possible sensations. In the light of this problem and advances in the logic of relations and
quantification, Peirce
further revised his account of the categories. He now [1885] referred
to them as Firstness, Secondness, and Thirdness respectively irreducible
monadic, dyadic, and triadic formal relations.But each category also has a material aspect in ideas
respectively, quality, 'thisness' (haecceity)
or 'existence' (he sometimes also referred to it as reaction), and mediation
(or representation) [g]. By quality he means a 'suchness', an immediate phenomenal datum given
in sensation [h] (for example, that
in an object which causes us to say it is red). The second is an
experience of an interaction of one
thing opposing another. Only individual
things possess 'thisness' [i]. The third refers to relations between things (usually sign relations),
and is an experience of thought or rationality. This third kind of idea is the
intellectual concept which can be clarified by the pragmatic method. This can be understood
as follows. While in its formal
(logical) aspect Thirdness mediates between signs and their interpretants, in
its material (ontological) aspect it mediates between Firstness and Secondness,
that is, between quality and 'thisness', and is manifested in laws of various
kinds. It is in this respect that Thirdness as mediational is
pragmatic: it involves consideration of
the real interrelatedness of all things in terms of means to ends [j].
KNOWLEDGE
[2] In Peirce's early theory it is
experience (representations, that is, phenomena and thoughts) which is primary.
The object is a supposition, grounded in hypothetical or inductive reasoning,
that experience can be organized, and
it exists as a cognition. However, he
supposed that representations
are material instantiations of divine
archetypes and qua concepts are
cognised by means of abstraction from intuited objects. He later [articles in Journal of Speculative Philosophy] argued that we identify relations in our sensations
and refer them to a common cause the object. But knowledge is, as it were, asymptotic and never
complete. Objects are real only in the
sense that they exist at the unachievable limit of converging series of
cognitions and as 'universals' in the collective experience, thought, and
descriptions of observers. (There are no individuals as such) [a]. Peirce said that the initial stimuli are not known; the emphasis is on
the build-up of relations. It is on the
basis of such coherent experience that an organism can develop habits or rules of behaviour the
consequences of which will satisfy its needs. He calls these habits beliefs. The search for such rules of
behaviour and for the best methods of enquiry constitutes and justifies science
(Peirce rejects the Cartesian method of universal doubt) [b]. He was committed to the
view that all human
knowledge is fallible. He talked
of propositions as being
true in that (a) they may express someone's belief (this is ethical truth); or
(b) they conform (and thus correspond) to reality (logical truth). By the latter he meant a proposition of
science and metaphysics is factually true so long as it can be empirically
tested as part of the process
of scientific enquiry. Thus far a belief
can be said to command a consensus. He
defines the process of enquiry in terms of the 'concordance' of an abstract
statement to the ideal limit "towards which endless investigation would tend to
bring scientific belief". Truth
is "absolute fixity of belief". We do
not of course always know beliefs to be true, but they remain probable until they are refuted and thereby shown to be false. Mathematical propositions can never be refuted because they have no reference. We therefore always know their truth [c].
The subsequent development of Peirce's theory of knowledge
[1885-1902] followed his revised view of the categories and involved his
attempt (1) to account for the perception of quality or 'thisness'; (2) to
reconcile the view of logic as a method for seeking belief with the view of
logic as the source of the universal categories and thus as the foundation of
knowledge. He offered a phenomenological analysis of
perception. He argued that
although we are conscious of percepts we cannot be said to know them. They are
given to us in intuition which is the result of unconscious inferences from
stimuli and the processes of synthesis. But we can make and
know 'explanatory' judgements about our percepts; and it is these judgements,
from which we can draw conscious inferences, that form the basis of our
knowledge. Peirce argued further
that that we empirically
observe the three categories in their material aspect [d], namely, 'quality', 'thisness', and 'mediation'.
METAPHYSICS
[3] [gen 3] Peirce's
epistemological concept of an ideal limit and his notion of logical truth as
the conformity of a proposition with reality suggest that the reality of an
object might be defined in terms of ultimate convergence of an enquiry. Moreover, in so far as predicates of a
judgement are of abstract and general attributes objects would seem to have an
ideal existence. Following his general
revision of category theory Peirce,
although critical of traditional metaphysics, developed an evolutionary cosmology grounded in the three
fundamental categories [see the Monist metaphysical articles]. He first derived three metaphysical modes
of being: real possibility,
actuality, and 'destiny' (relating to future facts), which correspond to the
three forms of experience, quality, fact, and mediation (involving regularity
and continuity). He identified further three modes of existence: chance, evolutionary interactions, and
tendencies to acquire habits (manifested in laws). (At the level of mind there are also three aspects of the cosmic
organism: feeling, volition, and
belief which the individual experiences as Firstness, Secondness, and
Thirdness). The activity of the universe
as a whole is explained by Peirce with reference to three corresponding principles [a]: (1) 'Tychism': the universe is supposed to, have been
initially in a state of pure undetermined or undifferentiated "chaos of
unpersonalized being" with only the bare possibility of spontaneous or
'chance' realization of 'suchness'. (2)
In the course of evolution qualities interact, and actualities progress towards
a final end of concrete rationality. This second stage of the universe's activity is called 'agapism'
(appertaining to 'law' of attraction, love). (3) As chance is deficit of habit, so the third stage is one of complete
regularity and absence of chance. Feeling and action are subordinated to belief-knowledge. Underlying this final stage ('synechism') is the concept of continuity. And Peirce utilizes the arguments of Zeno to
prove that space and time are continuous as referred to unactualized
possibilities [b]. Indeed, he says
the notion of discontinuous atoms is one which is not scientifically testable.
The system Peirce has developed is thus an objective idealism and monistic in that matter is mind
crystallized, as it were, by habits [c]. To the extent that Peirce believed in a God, It is regarded both as a
personal creator (the 'Absolute First') and as the end ('Absolute Second') of
the cosmos, fully revealed to the mind as a philosophical concept through
reason [d].
ETHICS
[4] It is in assisting the cosmic process to realize rationality, and
thereby to recognise and express in universal love his common interests with
the "unlimited community of mankind", that man finds the objective basis for
ethical action [a]. But Peirce distinguishes between pure and practical ethics. The
role of the former is to examine the nature of the end of ethical conduct the summum bonum. The job of practical ethics is to
determine how the end
might be achieved how practical consequences of inquiry (for which the social
context of the "community of inquirers"
is required) might be realized. Theory and practice, however, are
inseparable: thought is translated into
action through application of the pragmaticist method involving the logical
categories [b].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Peirce was a philosopher of great range and versatility, who combined detailed and
careful analysis with considerable speculative power. He is significant particularly for the
contributions he made to the development of modern logic and for his pragmatic
theory of meaning. His thought passed
through a number of stages of development, and although he continued throughout
his life to address himself to the same problems he did not really produce any
final 'system'. It might also be argued
that his unswerving commitment to a specific triadic 'architectonic' is suggestive
of a certain rigidity or formalism in his thinking. There are several particular difficulties
with his philosophy that should be noted here.
(1) (a) His
account of meaning and truth seems to commit him to the view that different
words which would appear in ordinary discourse to have different meanings must
mean the same if they have the same 'consequences'. (b) This raises the question whether we can
be sure what the 'practical consequences' of a particular word will be. Moreover (c), if such consequences are to
result 'by necessity' from the truth of such a conception, what kind of
necessity is this? If it is de dicto necessity, does this not beg
the question? If it is de re, we must ask how this is to be
known.
(2) As for the concept of truth itself, Peirce's
view is supposedly 'realist', in that it depends on a consensus of scientific
opinion. The notion of a 'convergence'
is, however, an assumption. His implicit
commitment to a correspondence theory also exposes him to the difficulties of
that theory though of course he is not alone in this respect. It can also be argued that there is a tension
between this 'realism' and his espousal of a 'linguistic idealist' world-view, in that, given indefiniteness of
reference of signs, any supposedly transcendent signified cannot be accessed.
(3) What practical
(scientific) consequences could be supposed to be relevant to the meaningful
use of the concept of a personal God as the end of an evolutionary cosmic
process?
Peirce: Of his many lectures and articles through which he developed his philosophy see in
particular 'On a New List of Categories' (1867), the three 1868 articles in The Journal of
Speculative Philosophy, 'The Fixation of Belief' (1877), 'How to Make Our
Ideas Clear' (1878), the Monist metaphysical articles (1891-1893), the Harvard lectures of 1903, and 'What
Pragmatism Is' (1905). Most of his work is accessible through the
two volume The Essential Peirce,
edited by N. Houser and C. Kloeser. Peirce Edition Project. See also Essential Writings ed. H. Moore.
Studies:
Introductory
W. B.
Gallie, Peirce and Pragmatism.
More advanced
C. Hookway, Peirce.
M. G. Murphey, The Development of Peirce's Philosophy.
M.
Thompson, The Pragmatic Philosophy of C.
S. Peirce.
Collections of essays
C. Misak (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Peirce.
P. P. Wiener and F.
H. Young (eds), Studies in the Philosophy
of Charles Sanders Peirce.
CONNECTIONS
Peirce