HOBBES
MATERIALISM
Hobbes was born near
Malmesbury, Wiltshire, the son of an 'ignorant' vicar, but was brought up by a
rich uncle. He was educated at the local
grammar school and then at Magdalen Hall (now Hertford College), Oxford, where
he became critical of the prevailing Aristotelianism. An appointment as tutor to the Cavendish
family in 1608 enabled him to spend time on the Continent; and his meetings
there with such famous figures as Galileo and Descartes were important for his
intellectual development, as was his friendship with Francis Bacon. Further posts in England followed, but in
1640 he was back in France for a much longer period, as his political views
were proving unpopular with the Long Parliament. While there he was for a time tutor to the
future Charles II of England and Scotland. The publication in 1651 of his famous Leviathan brought him into conflict with both the Catholic clergy
and the English Court in Exile for his supposed anti-royalism, so he returned
once more to England, though here too he was frequently attacked by all
Christian denominations for his Erastianism, that is, the subordination of
church to state, and his alleged atheism. He later acquired great renown as a translator of Latin and Greek classics.
[Sources: Page
references to Leviathan are those
of the original edition of 1651.]
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND LOGIC
NOMINALISM
[1] [Leviathan, ch. 4] Language for
Hobbes has two functions: (1) to help
the individual remember his thoughts in so far as they are 'transferred' into
words (words used in this way as 'marks' are called names); (2) to enable us
to communicate our thoughts to others by combining words into speech (words are
then acting as signs). His account of names is not altogether clear,
but he seems to have made the following distinctions. Considered in isolation a name is concrete and may denote a body, an
accident (quality), or indeed another name, which may be (a) a proper
name ('Peter', 'this man'); (b) a universal name (for example, 'man'
referring variously to any members of the class of men; or (c) a logical name
(such as 'universal' or 'species'). His position is thoroughly nominalist. The meaning of names consists in their denotation. Logical names are names of 'second
intention', whereas proper names and universal names are of 'first intention' [a]. Hobbes makes it clear that universals are only common names; they do not refer to essences, Platonic
Ideas, forms, or the like. Nothing universal corresponds in Nature to, say, 'humanity' or
'redness'. There are only individual things, which may have similar
features [b]. Further, when we combine names with other names (to form speech), as in,
for example, 'man is a living creature', we look for causes of concrete names or causes of corresponding
conceptions. This gives rise to abstract
names (for example, 'corporeity', 'motion'), which we attribute to 'accidents',
that is, qualities, or powers in the things we conceive. Names thus used are, however, not signs of
things themselves. It is on the basis
of his nominalist theory of language that he can establish definitions the "settling of significations of... words" [Lev. 4], and which, he says, are propositions whose predicates
"resolve the subject", when they may; or "exemplify it", when they may not [Concerning Body VI, sec. 14]. They are not to be taken as
giving the 'essences' of things [ibid. I, 5, 7] [c]. Hobbes also discusses the
misuse of words, which he says leads to error [Lev.
4, sec. 15] [d]. This can happen if we use, say, the word
'red' and assume there is an actual entity called redness in things. Likewise we are mistaken to suppose there is
an actual existing man when we say man is a living creature. Hence:
in
the right definition of names lies the first use of speech, which is the
acquisition of science: and in wrong, or
no definitions, lies the first abuse, from which proceed all false and
senseless tenets;... For words are wise men's counters, they do but reckon
by them: but they are the money of
fools, that value them by the authority of an Aristotle, a Cicero, or a Thomas,
[ibid.]
It follows from Hobbes' account of signs and definition that necessary truth, and indeed
logic and reasoning in general, is a matter of convention [e].
Reason gives us no conclusion about the nature of
things, but only about the terms that designate them, namely, whether or not
there is a convention (arbitrarily made aboiut their menaings) according to
which we join these names together. [Objections to Descartes' Meditations,
iii, 4.]
METHODOLOGY
[2] In his early writings [for example, Concerning Body] Hobbes says there are
two principal branches of philosophy natural and civil. The first is concerned with natural bodies,
that is, made by Nature, while the latter deals with 'commonwealths', which are
the political bodies made by the wills and agreements of men. Bodies can bring about effects by virtue of their motions; and
Hobbes considers these to be "the
one universal cause". We can have no
knowledge of causes except by reference to motions [a]. It is to discover causes thus understood and produce
explanations that he proposes two methods: (1) composition (or synthesis) the mind starts with
general principles or definitions and tries to derive possible effects. Such a procedure is deductive. (2) resolution
(analysis). This method is inductive: the mind starts from particulars and moves to
statements of universal first principles. Hobbes clearly supposed that these two methods are complementary. Thus we start with 'appearances'
(sense-experiences) and memories of them and formulate general hypotheses which
in turn may be tested by means of their observable effects. Hobbes intended to apply this methodology not only to 'inanimate'
Nature (as in mechanics, physics) but also to man and society (psychology,
ethics, and political philosophy) [see On the Citizen, Preface] [b]. However, by the time he wrote Leviathan there is little trace of a
rigid geometrical deductivism, and his moral philosophy is firmly grounded in
principles which he regarded as sufficiently known by experience. But he remained critical of over-reliance on experimental
procedures to establish scientific truth unless attention be made to the
epistemological and metaphysical assumptions implicit in the context in which
the results are interpreted [c]. As he wrote: "experience concludeth nothing universally" [Elements of Law I, 4, 10].
PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE
[3] Hobbes's philosophy
of nature includes 'first philosophy' (which is concerned with bodies having quantity and
motion), mathematics, physics, psychology, and even ethics (in so far as
man is natural body). Material bodies are assumed to
possess accidents [see Elements of
Law I, 2, 10], in the sense that we appeal to them to account for the production in us of
conceptions or thoughts. Some accidents
Hobbes supposes to be common to all bodies and to exist intrinsically in them,
for example, extension, magnitude, figure or shape. These perish when the body perishes. Other accidents, however, such as colour,
hardness, smell, can perish without the body disintegrating. Hobbes is here in effect making a distinction
between 'secondary' and
'primary' qualities [a]. Thus a hard body can become soft. It is clear that for him accidents as
capacities do not actually exist in bodies in the way they appear to us (as
'phantasms', that is, images) in our consciousness or at least if they did we
could not know this. He thinks they
arise as a result of the motions within the organism, which are in turn
reactions to local motions of other bodies. Space and time may be understood as imaginary or real according as to
whether they are accidents of the mind or of the body. As the former they are subjective
images: but to these there is an
objective ground in so far as 'real' space is identifiable with extension and
'real' time with succession of motions.
[4] Hobbes's descriptions of accidents provides
him with the basis for his account of causation [See Concerning Body II, 6-10]. The "entire cause" of an effect
consists of an efficient cause and a material cause. The former is the total collection of
accidents in the agent which are needed to produce a given effect, whereas the
material cause is the sum of accidents in the 'patient' or receiver of the effect. Hobbes also calls the efficient cause active power when it is referred
to the future rather than to an actual
effect; and in the same way material
cause is called passive power. He further rejects the notions
of formal and final cause; both, he
says, can be reduced to efficient causes [ibid. II, 10, 7] [a]. The form or
'essence' of a thing can only be the cause of knowledge of that thing. Final causality relates to man's deliberation
about ends and therefore must refer to the way efficient causality
operates. His account of causation thus seems to be deterministic
and mechanistic: effects follow
from their causes necessarily and instantaneously. Cause and effect are both physically and
logically inseparable involving as they do transfer of motion by one body to another [a]. We cannot therefore conceive of an effect if
any one of its 'entire' cause is absent. Hobbes says also that we do not always know in a particular case what
the antecedent cause of an effect actually is.
PSYCHOLOGY
[5] [Concerning Body II, 8; IV, 25; Leviathan, ch. 6.] Hobbes extends his materialist philosophy
uncompromisingly to psychology. He tries
to account for man's
mental life and behaviour entirely in terms of motions of extended bodies [a]. If it is legitimate to
speak at all of a 'soul' or 'spirit', it must be understood as being a 'subtle'
or 'fluid' body. He distinguishes two
kinds of motions (found in animals as well as man): (1) vital motions, for example, the
circulation of blood, respiration, digestion processes which happen by
themselves, without any conscious control or deliberation; (2) 'voluntary' or
'animal' motions. For these latter to
occur we need first to receive external motions from the accidents in other bodies. These bring about internal motions manifested
in imagination: we have images of
motions such as speaking or moving a leg. These in turn produce the
"small beginnings of motion within the body", which Hobbes calls endeavour (conatus), and which eventually appear in our bodily actions [b]. Other images are of colours, sounds, smells,
and the like, which constitute our perception; and we also have dream
images. If endeavour is directed towards
its cause, it is called appetite or desire; but if away from the cause,
aversion. If the relevant motions are
experienced in the brain they are conceptions or thoughts (which Hobbes seems
also to identify with images); but if continued on to the heart they are said
to be passions such as love or joy (desires), or hate and grief (aversions). Hobbes rejects any notion of a 'will' as
such; what we call will or
volition, he says, is but the last appetite or aversion in the whole chain of
our passions, which leads to action. This suggests a
deterministic account of the causal processes constituting human choice and
action. To have liberty for Hobbes is to be free of external restraint on our
motions [c].
KNOWLEDGE
[6] [See, for example, Concerning
Body I, 1; Leviathan, ch.
9.] "...the object is one thing, the
image or fancy is another", Hobbes says
[Leviathan, ch. 1]. Now, given that accidents such as colour,
taste, and so on belong to the perceiver, what of the spatially extended bodies
which supposedly really exist in the external world? How can we know that they exist? It is possible that only oneself exists,
perhaps possessing a language of one's own but a language the relationship of
which to reality we can know nothing about? Perhaps there is only the thinker, understood as but a sequence of inner
'phantasms'. While agreeing with Descartes' 'cogito' argument, he tries to avoid the
solipsistic position by appealing to the evidence of change [see notes
to Elements of Philosophy I; Concerning Body I; cf. Objections to
Descartes' Meditations.] Because our thoughts are continually changing we must attribute them to
external causes, as nothing can move itself; and such moving bodies must be
extended in real space [a]. To explain our knowledge
Hobbes distinguishes [Leviathan, ch.
9] between knowledge of
facts ('effects') and knowledge of consequences. The former is grounded ultimately in
'appearances', that is, sense-impressions, and our memory images of them
(called 'absolute'). Knowledge of
consequences, which he regards as scientific of philosophical knowledge, is
knowledge of facts and of the way in
which they have been generated, namely through a causal process [b]. This is to be understood
in terms of a deductive procedure. Knowledge of consequences is thus
hypothetical or conditional, in so far as the conclusion depends on the
premisses which for Hobbes are ideally the general principles or
'definitions' of his synthetic method. It follows also that we
can have no philosophical knowledge of any 'spiritual' God or even of history in so far as the latter appeals to memory experiences and not 'ratiocination' [Concerning Body I, 1, 8ff.]. Where he does talk about God it is always as a 'corporeal spirit' [c]. He stresses that philosophical knowledge is
essentially practical in that it should lead to man's material well-being and
social security. "The end of knowledge
is power [d]... and the scope of all speculation is
the performance of some action or thing to be done" [Concerning Body I, 1, 6].
ETHICS/ POLITICAL
PHILOSOPHY
SOCIAL
CONTRACT THEORY
[7] "The true moral philosophy" for Hobbes
is the 'science' of good and evil, that is, the study of the (human) laws of
nature. 'Good' and 'evil'
are defined by individuals in terms of their own passions: "whatsoever is the object of any man's
appetite or desire, that is it which he for his part calls good: and the object of his
hate, aversion, evil". [Lev.,
ch. 6, p. 24; cf. On the Citizen III, 31.] It
follows that there is no
objective good and evil [a], each man's
'voluntary' motions being different. The
notion of an individual considered as prior to or separate from society is,
however, for Hobbes and abstraction and not a historical fact; and his ethics
is therefore best understood in the context of his political philosophy.
Individual humans, being material bodies and
driven essentially by their appetites and aversions, must inevitably come into
conflict if they are in what Hobbes calls the natural state a hypothetical
concept [b]. He identifies three causes of dispute: competition, 'diffidence' (mistrust), and
glory or the desire for personal fame [Lev., ch. 13]. They also disagree about what is good or bad. They live, Hobbes says, in a constant fear of death. Though they may not always be actually fighting
they remain in a state of readiness for war. Man's life is "solitary, poor,
nasty, brutish, and short" [Lev., ch.
13, p. 62]. However, though motivated by their passions, men are also
rational. And Hobbes says [Lev., ch. 14, p. 64] that reason reveals to us a general
rule which contains (1) "the first and fundamental law
of nature" that man ought to seek his (own)
peace and follow it; (2) the natural right to
self-preservation, which tells us that to the extent we cannot obtain
peace we should use all the means we can to defend ourselves. And we cannot renounce this right if
we are to be consistent with ourselves as a rational human beings. Hobbes stresses that right consists in liberty (in his special sense),
while law imposes obligations. From the first law he claims to derive
eighteen more [see chs 14 and 15]. The second [pp. 64-5] states that in his
pursuit of peace a man
should be willing to renounce his right to self-defence provided others renounce theirs, that is, give up their liberty to
hinder him [c]. This gives rise to a social contract, or, if one of the contractors is left
to perform his part at a later date, a covenant [pp. 66ff.] The third law is then that men should perform
the covenants they have made. Now to ensure that covenants are
fulfilled individuals agree to transfer their rights to one person or an assembly
of persons. Hobbes calls this 'artefact' the Sovereign or Commonwealth the "Great Leviathan or mortal god,
to which we owe under the Immortal God, our peace and defence" [Lev. ch. 17, p. 87]. He stresses that covenants are made between individuals and not
with the Sovereign whose subjects they will be. This is because the
centralizing of authority will prevent a division of power, and because power
can be enforceable by the sword (and comes into being with the covenant
itself). The commonwealth
may be a monarchy (which Hobbes favours), a democracy, or an aristocracy [d], depending on its effectiveness in
preserving peace. The commonwealth thus described has been established by what
Hobbes calls 'institution', that is, through agreement. But he also allows for
a commonwealth by 'acquisition' through force. But the rights of the
Sovereign [Lev., 18] are the same in
both. He has absolute inalienable power
(he cannot give it away), though he can delegate others (individuals or a
parliament) to act on his behalf. The Sovereign determines what is
right or wrong (and thereby what is 'just' and 'unjust') and lays down the
civil laws [e] required to
preserve the peace and guarantee to all "commodious living". Hobbes accepts that the Sovereign must be obeyed in all things
relevant even if this involves curtailment of freedom of opinon and
expression; for it is law that protects the individual against violence from
others, removes restraints. But this
guarantees natural liberty in so far as this consists on the absence of
external hindrances to motion [f]. The killing of enemies of the state, however, is justified if the action
is performed so as to preserve the commonwealth. Where self-protection is not
the issue in any given matter, the individual may legitimately refuse to obey
the Sovereign's command (though he may still be punished for disobedience).
There are also a number of areas of human life with which the Sovereign does
not interfere, such as where one decides to live, what to eat, and so on. As each subject is the author of the
Sovereign's actions (by virtue of his empowerment through the social contract),
the Sovereign himself cannot be punished or put to death; for he always acts in
their name, and in effect one subject would be punishing another. another. Although the Sovereign has been
given absolute power, the right of the individual to self-preservation remains
paramount; and Hobbes says [Lev.,
ch. 21] that should a
Sovereign fail to guarantee liberty and afford protection to those who
have placed him in authority they
would have the right to depose him and seek another [g]. Even the prisoner sentenced to death has the
right to resist. As for the Sovereign's
relationship to the Church, Hobbes had said in his On the Citizen that
responsibility for interpreting the scriptures should be accorded to the
latter, and that any interpretation the Sovereign might attempt should be
effected through the clergy. However,
in the Leviathan [ch. 42] he changed his position and argued that interpretation should be the exclusive prerogative of the
Sovereign, and indeed that the
Church should be subordinate to the Sovereign's decrees [h].
CRITICAL SUMMARY
Hobbes is known primarily
for his outstanding work in political philosophy. However, his contribution to other areas of
philosophy should not be underestimated not least because of his rejection of
rationalist metaphysics, scholasticism and all theological assumptions.
(1) His discussion of the
misuse of language is important and influential.. But his linguistic nominalism
(which can be seen as anticipating twentieth century structuralism) is open to
objections. Not all words 'name' things;
and some of Hobbes's distinctions are not as clear as one would wish. Furthermore, to the extent that privacy is
implicit in what seems to be his view that thought is separable from and prior
to language, it is arguable that the way to a public world of shared meaning is
blocked. Similarly, given that
definitions are of names which apply to 'cogitations', there is a problem
concerning the application of science to the external world: although Hobbes
does presuppose the existence of bodies, his assumptions would seem to require
him to be committed to scepticism in this respect.
(2) His mechanistic-materialistic account of
nature, including human psychology. While it might be claimed that a merit of his theory is that it
dispenses with any notion of an abstract 'will' there is a problem in that it
is difficult to accommodate the idea of free choice within this framework. Moreover, his limited view of freedom, which
he defines as the absence of external restraint, can be regarded as a narrow
basis on which to base an account of human action sufficient to underpin his
social and ethical philosophy. His rejection of voluntarism also sits uneasily
with his statement in the Leviathan that
men ought to seek peace, the 'will'
for him being but the last appetite or aversion in the causal chain leading to
action.
(3) Hobbes appeals to a universal deductive-inductive methodology, but arguably
this is not fully worked out. For
example, he starts with definitions grounded in sense-experience and deduces
effects, but he seems to underestimate the role of experiment. Moreover, despite his intention to apply the
method universally, it is not strictly adhered to in his socio-political
philosophy, in that he does not attempt a rigorous deduction of first
principles of political 'science' from 'motions' as causes but starts from a
consideration of the hypothetical 'state of nature' and its consequences. His failure to do so, however, can well be
seen as a point in his favour.
(4) The central ideas of his social and political philosophy,
especially the social contract and the Absolute Sovereign are of great
importance. But here too there are difficulties. Firstly it is unclear whether Hobbes's
'ought' is to be understood ethically (in which case the Humean objection to
any move from fact to value can be raised), or whether he is making the point
that it would be contrary to reason for human beings not to seek to preserve
themselves and therefore peace. Further
he does not provide an adequate account of how individuals in the chaos of the
natural state might establish the contract in the first place. His view of man can also be regarded as
unduly negative and limited. It is
certainly a matter for debate whether egoism and hedonism are the only or even
the primary motivating forces underlying human behaviour. Many sociobiologists today argue that human
altruism and feelings of sympathy for others are grounded in human 'nature' and
that sociability is a natural condition. As for the Sovereign, the view that Hobbes's conception is of a
totalitarian dictator is probably exaggerated, not least because Hobbes allows
that his powers may be delegated to other individuals or committees and that he
must therefore rely on their cooperation. Moreover, the Sovereign too is human; and one can suppose it would be in
his own best interests to rule justly so as to ensure the safety and commodious
living of his subjects. Hobbes makes it clear that should he fail to do so then
it would be right for the people to depose him. The problem here of course is
how they are to determine that he is in fact failing in his responsibilities.
Who is to judge? By what criteria? The practicality of removing him may also
not have been fully considered by Hobbes for all his experience of the Civil
War.
CONNECTIONS
Hobbes
Note: Hobbes's general rejection of Aristotelian scholasticism; also the
influence on him of Galileo [1564-1632] (methodology; primary and secondary
qualities), and Grotius [1583-1645] (ethical and political thought), through
whose The Laws of War and Peace many views of the Stoics were also
mediated.